I have cheated and replaced the first version with a second version a week later.
Recovery, paternalism and narrative understanding in mental healthcare
Recovery, paternalism and narrative understanding in mental healthcare
Abstract
There has been a growing emphasis on the idea that recovery in mental
healthcare should not be seen as a matter of getting better but instead of successfully
living a flourishing life as conceived by the subject herself. Theorists of recovery
also stress the importance of narrative understanding for articulating the sort
of life that would count as recovery. But surely one of the threats of mental illness
is that it can undermine a subject’s autonomy and hence capacity to author a suitable
narrative for recovery? Addressing this worry raises the threat of paternalism.
Having sketched an abstract model of recovery and compared it to the capabilities
model of Sen and Nussbaum, this chapter outlines a minimal account of narrative
understanding drawn from Peter Goldie’s book The Mess Inside can address the worry of paternalism.
Introduction: Recovery as the
goal of mental healthcare.
In this first section, I introduce recovery as the goal of mental
healthcare and sketch an abstract model for it. Recovery aims at a value-laden
and person specific conception of flourishing. In the second section, I show
how the capabilities approach of Amartya Sen and Martha Nussbaum fits this
abstract model but that the difference between Nussbaum’s and Sen’s versions reflects
a corresponding difference between substantive and procedural accounts of
personal autonomy. This difference is also present in Davidson and Hopper’s
more specific claims about the possibilities for recovery from mental illness
and leads to a challenge to the recovery model. If mental illness can compromise
autonomy and calls for sensitive clinical intervention to recover it, does this
not risk the paternalist imposition of others’ values? In the final two
sections I argue that a narrative view of a sense of self can address this on
either opposed broad view of recovery and autonomy.
Recovery has come to be promoted as a novel and desirable target for
mental healthcare. It has become a proud boast that mental healthcare is recovery
orientated. Nevertheless, whilst there is agreement that in this context, it does
not mean merely getting better or returning to a previous state of health, there
remains disagreement as to what recovery is.
There is an increasing global commitment to recovery as the
expectation for people with mental illness. There remains, however, little consensus
on what recovery means in relation to mental illness. [Davidson and Roe 2007: 450]
The term ‘recovery’ appears to have a simple and self-evident
meaning, but within the recovery literature it has been variously used to mean an
approach, a model, a philosophy, a paradigm, a movement, a vision and, sceptically,
a myth. [Roberts and Wolfson 2004: 38]
In the UK,
a policy paper published by the Sainsbury Centre for Mental Health, titled ‘Making
recovery a reality’, begins by summarising some key points of emphasis which, it
is suggested, characterise any broadly conceived recovery-based approach. These
points include:
Recovery is about building a meaningful and satisfying
life, as defined by the person themselves, whether or not there are ongoing or recurring
symptoms or problems.
Recovery represents a movement away from pathology, illness and symptoms to health, strengths and wellness.
Hope is central to recovery and can be enhanced by each person seeing how they can have more active control over their lives (‘agency’) and by seeing how others have found a way forward.
Self-management is encouraged and facilitated. The processes of self-management are similar, but what works may be very different for each individual. No ‘one size fits all’.
The helping relationship between clinicians and patients moves away from being expert / patient to being ‘coaches’ or ‘partners’ on a journey of discovery. Clinicians are there to be “on tap, not on top”.
People do not recover in isolation. Recovery is closely associated with social inclusion and being able to take on meaningful and satisfying social roles within local communities, rather than in segregated services.
Recovery is about discovering – or re-discovering – a sense of personal identity, separate from illness or disability. [Shepherd, Boardman and Slade 2008: 0]
Recovery represents a movement away from pathology, illness and symptoms to health, strengths and wellness.
Hope is central to recovery and can be enhanced by each person seeing how they can have more active control over their lives (‘agency’) and by seeing how others have found a way forward.
Self-management is encouraged and facilitated. The processes of self-management are similar, but what works may be very different for each individual. No ‘one size fits all’.
The helping relationship between clinicians and patients moves away from being expert / patient to being ‘coaches’ or ‘partners’ on a journey of discovery. Clinicians are there to be “on tap, not on top”.
People do not recover in isolation. Recovery is closely associated with social inclusion and being able to take on meaningful and satisfying social roles within local communities, rather than in segregated services.
Recovery is about discovering – or re-discovering – a sense of personal identity, separate from illness or disability. [Shepherd, Boardman and Slade 2008: 0]
The Scottish Recovery Network summarises its views of
recovery in similar terms:
Recovery is about living a satisfying and fulfilling life.
Recovery is about more than the absence of the symptoms of illness. Some people describe themselves as being in recovery whilst still experiencing symptoms.
There can be lots of ups and downs during the recovery process – some people describe it as a journey.
For this reason people often talk about being in recovery rather than recovered.
Some people consider recovery as being ‘back to the way things were’ or back to ‘normal’ but for others recovery is more about discovering a new life or a new way of being. [Brown and Kandirikirira 2007: 3]
Recovery is about more than the absence of the symptoms of illness. Some people describe themselves as being in recovery whilst still experiencing symptoms.
There can be lots of ups and downs during the recovery process – some people describe it as a journey.
For this reason people often talk about being in recovery rather than recovered.
Some people consider recovery as being ‘back to the way things were’ or back to ‘normal’ but for others recovery is more about discovering a new life or a new way of being. [Brown and Kandirikirira 2007: 3]
These lists provide a starting point for setting out a theoretical
model of recovery. But there is a further structural constraint. To articulate a recovery model
which is distinct from or contrasts with, for example, a bio-medical model of mental
healthcare, it is not enough to say that recovery (construed in some broad way)
is a desirable aim of mental health care. One could hold that whilst holding a broadly
bio-medical view of health and illness: for example, as pertaining to biological
function versus dysfunction. To count as a distinct model of healthcare, it must
offer more than just a broad aim but rather a theoretical conception of what illness,
or health, or something like health is. (In the UK, the rise of the recovery
movement coincided with both greater optimism within biological psychiatry of the
efficacy of medicines but also the kind of theoretical articulation of a novel view
of recovery with which I am here concerned. Both elements played a role, complicating
the historical story.)
The characterisations of recovery above suggest the importance of
two distinctions. First, there is a distinction of focus between pathology and whatever
is its relevant contrast, perhaps health. Second, there is the distinction between
what is evaluative or normative and what is merely plainly factual. Together these
can be used to sketch a distinct although abstract conception of recovery. I will
take each in turn.
The philosophy of psychiatry, and more generally the philosophy of
medicine, has tended to focus on the illness end of a spectrum between health and
illness. The key concern has been with the notion of illness (or disease or disorder).
One reason for that has been the origin of the debate, at least within the philosophy
of psychiatry, in the response to Thomas Szasz’ argument that mental illness is
a myth [Szasz 1972]. Szasz’ claim that mental illness is an oxymoron prompted responses
by biologically minded psychiatrists and researchers who attempted to devise models
of illness (or disease or disorder) which accommodated not only physical but also
mental illness [Kendell 1975, Boorse 1975]. That in turn has led to an ongoing debate
focusing squarely on ill health [Fulford 1989, Pickering 2006, Wakefield 1999].
There was no equivalent Szaszian argument for the mythic status of mental health and hence no incentive for a philosophical
defence of that notion.
Against a background focus on the nature of illness, recovery can
seem to be simply a return from, or a removal of, that status. Whatever illness
or disease is, recovery is its negation. By contrast, concentration first on the
health end of the spectrum is at the heart of the recovery approach. This accords
with the claim quoted from the document ‘Making recovery a reality’ above that ‘Recovery represents a movement
away from pathology, illness and symptoms to health, strengths and wellness’.
A recovery model has to do more than just take the aim of healthcare to be the removal
of illness.
The second distinction is between views of mental illness in particular,
or illness more generally, as necessarily evaluative or merely descriptive. Does
the analysis of mental illness contain reference to values or not? Some philosophers
and psychiatrists argue that at the heart of the idea of illness is something that
is either bad or wrong for a sufferer or is a deviation from a social or moral norm.
Both of these are evaluative or normative notions and hence both are views of illness
as value-laden.
Others argue that illness is a plainly factual matter. Typically,
they argue that illness involves a failure of a biological function and that function
– and hence deviation from, or failure of, function – is a plainly factual, biological
(and/or psychological) term couched in evolutionary theory.
Having sketched the two distinctions, I suggest that a clue to articulating
a recovery model which genuinely contrasts with a medical model is to locate it
on the health-focused rather than pathology-focused side of the first distinction
and on the values-laden or normative side of the second.
That remains just a clue: more conceptual work has to be done. But
it might be objected that the first of these two distinctions is unnecessary; we
can articulate a genuine contrast to a bio-medical model simply by using the second
distinction.
The idea is that a bio-medical model construes mental illness as value-free,
as reducible to plain facts about biological (and/or psychological) function. Adopting
the opposite view – that illness is a necessarily evaluative notion – stands in
genuine contrast. And a conception of recovery in relation to illness, so construed,
might be enough to count as a recovery model because of that genuine, substantive
contrast.
Whilst such a position is a genuine contrast to a plausible candidate
for a bio-medical model of illness, it does not seem to capture an important element
of the recovery approach: a particular goal or aim of therapy which is not defined
merely as the absence of illness. It is instead captured in specific terms such
as a hope, autonomy and social inclusion.
One specific problem is that even if one thinks of illness as a necessarily
evaluative notion, this is not a sufficient reason to think that health is. It might
be the mere absence of an evaluatively identified illness state. Health might be conceptualized in merely
statistically normal (rather than normative or evaluative) terms, perhaps as the
state of most people, or, alternatively, the state one was previously in. If so,
whilst the states that individuals have an interest in recovering from are those
with particular normative or evaluative properties (whatever those are), recovery
itself might be characterized in non-normative non-evaluative terms. And that does
not seem to fit the way the recovery approach is characterized by its supporters.
What of the other distinction? Could a recovery model be defined simply
as one which focuses on a positive conception of health, or something like it, rather
than merely the absence of pathology, however construed? Again, no. As the authors
of ‘Making recovery a reality’
make plain, they have a very particular conception of the aim of recovery tied to
a conception of hoped for and autonomous life connected to social inclusion. That
specific content is not captured merely by a focus on health which, as I have just
argued, might be thought of in statistical normal terms.
To capture
what is characteristic of a recovery approach in order to frame a recovery model,
it seems that both aspects are needed: a) a focus on a conception of health, or
something like it, and b) in normative or evaluative terms. A recovery model is
thus one which construes the positive aim of mental healthcare to be a state of
health or something like it, necessarily characterised in normative or evaluative
terms.
The capabilities approach to recovery
The model
sketched above abstracts from typical comments made about the nature of recovery
in mental healthcare in practical policy documents. The idea that recovery aims
at a value-laden conception of a flourishing life, which is tailored to the individual
concerned, fits such documents. But that is not to say that that is the most that
might be offered by way of theoretical articulation of recovery. More can, and has
been, said which is, nevertheless, consistent with the abstract model just sketched.
In this section, I will outline an influential theoretical framework for thinking
about recovery: the capabilities approach. I will use this to extract a potential
tension in thinking about the value-ladenness and person-centeredness of recovery
and thus flag the role, in the next section for narrative.
The capabilities
approach to recovery in mental healthcare is based on Amartya Sen’s model for welfare
economics developed in the 1980s. Rather than focusing on the fair distribution of resources or primary goods,
Sen proposes that the focus of welfare economics should be on a fair distribution of the capacity to lead a flourishing
life. In this context, capability is a measure of the ability to do the things and
to be the ways that amount to a flourishing form of life. Sen uses the word ‘functionings’
for this latter idea.
The expression [‘capability’] was picked to represent the alternative
combinations of things a person is able to do or be-the various ‘functionings’ he
or she can achieve. The capability approach to a person’s advantage is concerned
with evaluating it in terms of his or her actual ability to achieve various valuable
functionings as a part of living… Functionings represent parts of the state
of a person-in particular the various things that he or she manages to do or be
in leading a life. The capability of a person reflects the alternative combinations
of functionings the person can achieve, and from which he or she can choose one
collection… Some functionings are very elementary, such as being adequately nourished,
being in good health, etc., and these may be strongly valued by all, for obvious
reasons. Others may be more complex, but still widely valued, such as achieving
self-respect or being socially integrated. Individuals may, however, differ a good
deal from each other in the weights they attach to these different functionings-valuable
though they may all be-and the assessment of individual and social advantages must
be alive to these variations. [Sen 1993 :31]
Applied to
welfare economics, the approach takes account of the fact that people can differ in the resources they need to achieve
valuable ways of being and acting. Hence it delivers different results from simply
advocating equal distributions of resources or primary goods.
In characterising capability, Sen stresses the role of freedom. The freedom
to live different kinds of life is reflected in a person’s set of capabilities.
Freedom itself adds value to a life. Even the existence of possibilities not adopted
or embraced add, via a sense of freedom, to the value of a life. But the relevant
sense of freedom does not range over just any possible life. Having the option to
live kinds of life that an individual would never consider is not freedom in Sen’s
sense. Genuine freedom has to be assessed relative to what a subject values. Further,
what is valued changes what counts as ‘functioning’. Fasting and starving both involve
the deprivation of food but because the former is chosen it counts as functioning.
This sensitivity of what counts as capability fits the value-ladenness and
person-centredness of the abstract model of recovery outlined in the previous section
of this chapter. It also fits the focus not on pathology but on health or flourishing.
The aim of recovery, on such an understanding, is to maximise the capability of
a person to achieve various valuable functionings as a part of their life.
It thus connects the abstract requirements on a recovery model to some pre-existing
philosophical and economic thinking. But this connection also highlights a tension
in, or challenge for, the recovery model which, in the next two sections, will be
connected to the role of narrative.
Despite the importance of freedom there is an important tension in thinking
about capability because of a second influence on its initial articulation: the
Aristotelian philosopher Martha Nussbaum. Nussbaum draws on Aristotle’s account
of flourishing to argue that there is a list of basic human functions that
applies to all human beings [Nussbaum 1988: 176]. Not just anything could count as human functioning.
Thus drawing on Aristotle, Nussbaum argues for universal standards for assessing
human capability. This contrasts with Sen’s liberal or relativist view that with
freedom comes proper diversity of choice. This forms the basis in the The Tanner Lectures on Human
Values of one of his criticisms of traditional welfare economics based on the
fair distribution of resources
or primary goods [Sen 1980].
In the co-authored
introduction to a collection of papers on the capabilities approach, Nussbaum and
Sen jointly set out the difficulties that apply to the choice between pressing a
universal or a culturally relative view of human capabilities. It is worth
quoting this passage at length.
Should we, for example, look to the local traditions of the country
or region with which we are concerned, asking what these traditions have regarded
as most essential to thriving, or should we, instead, seek some more universal account
of good human living, assessing the various local traditions against it? This question
needs to be approached with considerable sensitivity, and there appear to be serious
problems whichever route we take. If we stick to local traditions, this seems to
have the advantage of giving us something definite to point to and a clear way of
knowing what we want to know... It seems, as well, to promise the advantage of respect
for difference: instead of telling people in distant parts of the world what they
ought to do and to be, the choice is left to them. On the other hand, most traditions
contain elements of injustice and oppression, often deeply rooted; and it is frequently
hard to find a basis for criticism of these inequities without thinking about human
functioning in a more critical and universal way…The search for a universally applicable
account of the quality of human life has, on its side, the promise of a greater
power to stand up for the lives of those whom tradition has oppressed or marginalized.
But it faces the epistemological difficulty of grounding such an account in an adequate
way, saying where the norms come from and how they can be known to be the best.
It faces, too, the ethical danger of paternalism, for it is obvious that all too
often such accounts have been insensitive to much that is of worth and value in
the lives of people in other parts of the world and have served as an excuse for
not looking very deeply into these lives. [Nussbaum and Sen 1993: 4]
Uncritical relativism
versus paternalism is an apparent rather than actual dilemma, however. Each is the criticism that
someone taking the corresponding opposed view might make. Universalists fear
uncritical relativism but are in turn accused of paternalism by their opponents
who emphasise diversity. To
see this it is worth flagging corresponding opposed views of autonomy since
paternalism is the trumping of another's autonomy.
The idea
that universal standards of human flourishing necessarily threatens paternalism
presupposes that autonomy really is autonomous of external standards. One such
view is proceduralism equates base autonomy with the capacity of a
subject to reflect on and endorse, at a second order level, their first order
actions and values [eg Frankfurt 1971]. But it remains neutral as to what those
first order actions and values are. Substantive approaches, by contrast, argue
that the notion of autonomy involves an ability to be guided by the good and
the true. And hence a specification of what it is to be autonomous cannot avoid
substantive claims about human flourishing [eg Wolf 1990].
Clearly
if the very idea of autonomy presupposes tracking some universal standards,
then the mere existence of such standards cannot threaten the ethical danger of
paternalism, the unwarranted undermining of autonomy. If, on the other hand,
one thinks that autonomy is merely a matter of reflective coherence, then the
absence of universal standards is not a threat of uncritical relativism, it is
just that criticism is a matter of local coherence.
This opposition
within accounts of autonomy and versions of a capabilities approach to welfare
economics also has an echo in its application to the recovery model in mental
healthcare. In their paper ‘A Capabilities Approach to Mental Health
Transformation: A Conceptual Framework for the Recovery Era’, Larry Davidson and
colleagues follow Sen in stressing the connection between a capabilities approach
to recovery and the proper diversity of choices that will be made:
It is in the very nature of choice to result in variability, otherwise
choice would not really be free but would refer only to changes in the quantity
of some basic universal. While smoked salmon and french fries are, in fact, both
foods, to say that a person who prefers smoked salmon to french fries has no real
preference because they are both foods is to miss the point of having preferences
to begin with. It is to gloss over the issue of choice, but this is precisely where
our primary interest lies. Without choice there is no freedom, and therefore no
justice; with choice there inevitably will be differences and diversity. [Davidson
et al 2009: 42]
The view could be described as ‘liberal’ or ‘procedural’. It stresses the
role of freedom and the proper diversity of responses to its exercise. By contrast,
Kim Hopper argues in his paper ‘Rethinking social recovery in schizophrenia: what
a capabilities approach might offer’ that:
Any application of capabilities
must therefore first define/defend a (full or partial) list of valued functionings...
[Hopper 2007: 876]
Hopper follows Nussbaum following Aristotle in assuming some objective and
universally applicable limits to the proper exercise of choice and freedom. An objective
and substantive list of valued functionings would be an objective standard independent
of individual choices and that might, in principle at least serves as standards
of correctness for them. That is, it makes sense on Hopper’s view to think that
someone might be in error about the nature of their own flourishing. They might
be able to follow the correct procedures of second order reflection on first
order values but be in error about objective values at both levels. That possibility
is ruled out on a liberal or procedural view.
A similar contrast is also evident concerning the authenticity of choice.
Davidson et al claim that mental illness does not affect the status as an agent
of individuals.
There can be no recovery without self-determination… Mental
illness may pose an obstacle to the person’s achievement of the kind of life he
or she wishes to have, may make it more difficult to live that life, and, at its
most extreme, may even deprive the person of life altogether. In none of these cases,
though, does mental illness fundamentally alter the basic nature of human beings,
which is that of being self-determined agents, free to choose and pursue the kind
of life they as individuals value. Mental illness does not rob people of their
agency, nor does it deprive them of their fundamental civil rights. [Davidson
2009: 4-1 italics added]
By contrast
Hopper warns that the choices made people with mental illnesses may lack authenticity.
Their choices may be affected or distorted as a consequence of illness itself or
their treatment as a result of that illness.
Deprivation and disgrace can so corrode one’s self worth that
aspiration can be distorted, initiative undercut and preferences deformed. Sensitive
work will be needed to recover that suppressed sense of injustice and reclaim lost
possibility. [Hopper 2007: 877]
Whichever
view one takes of the local and diverse or universal view of capabilities and
the corresponding opposition between procedural versus substantive view of
autonomy, Hopper’s point is surely empirically correct. The stigma of carrying a
mental illness diagnosis is often reported to be as disabling as the mental itself
[Corrigan and Watson 2002].
That raises the possibility of an indirect connection – mediated by medical and
broader societal treatment – between illness and aspiration. But there are also
direct connections. In his study of the phenomenology of depression, Matthew Ratcliffe
reports that in severe depression not only is motivation undermined but awareness
of the very possibilities for action diminish. Objects are no longer imbued with
the possibilities for action. So it is not just that there are possible actions
which the sufferer feels incapable of taking up. Rather, the sense of such possibilities
also vanishes. In extreme cases, this undermines an understanding of other people’s
purposive actions.
[M]ore profound losses involve an inability to comprehend the
possibility of anything being practically significant for anyone:
But in among the bad and worse times, there were also moments when I felt, if not hope, then at least the glimmerings of possibility… It was like starting from the beginning. It took me a long time, for example, to understand, or to re-understand, why people do things. Why, in fact, they do anything at all. What is it that occupies their time? What is the point of doing? During my long morning walks, I watched people hurrying along in suits and trainers. Where was it they were going, and why were they in such haste? I simply couldn’t imagine feeling such urgency. I watched others throwing a ball for a dog, picking it up, and throwing it again. Why? Where was the sense in such pointless repetition? [Brampton, 2008, p.249]
This description of the ‘return of possibility’ serves to make salient what was previously diminished or lost: a sense of what it is for someone to act purposively, to find things significant and respond to them accordingly. Activities such as playing with a ball or hurrying to a destination had become strange, unfamiliar, bereft of meaning. The depressed person therefore experiences her situation as something she cannot act upon. [Ratcliffe 2015: 167]
But in among the bad and worse times, there were also moments when I felt, if not hope, then at least the glimmerings of possibility… It was like starting from the beginning. It took me a long time, for example, to understand, or to re-understand, why people do things. Why, in fact, they do anything at all. What is it that occupies their time? What is the point of doing? During my long morning walks, I watched people hurrying along in suits and trainers. Where was it they were going, and why were they in such haste? I simply couldn’t imagine feeling such urgency. I watched others throwing a ball for a dog, picking it up, and throwing it again. Why? Where was the sense in such pointless repetition? [Brampton, 2008, p.249]
This description of the ‘return of possibility’ serves to make salient what was previously diminished or lost: a sense of what it is for someone to act purposively, to find things significant and respond to them accordingly. Activities such as playing with a ball or hurrying to a destination had become strange, unfamiliar, bereft of meaning. The depressed person therefore experiences her situation as something she cannot act upon. [Ratcliffe 2015: 167]
The examples Ratcliffe describes suggest that Davidson et al are wrong to
deny that mental illnesses can rob people of their agency. Such a connection to
agency seems, to the contrary, to be a key element in the way that mental illnesses
cause harm. This may not be so obvious in in schizophrenia, for example, but it
is still plausible to think that delusions disrupt the formation of intentions
for action [Fulford 1989]. Perhaps the reason Davidson makes that claim is a confusion
with, or assimilation to, the claim that follows: ‘nor does it deprive them of their
fundamental civil rights’. This claim might express the following warning. One should
not assume that just because someone has a mental illness that they therefore forfeit
fundamental civil rights premised on the idea of being an autonomous human agents.
But even this claim has to accommodate the complication of legal detention and compulsory
treatment under mental health legislation. Such a widely held legal principle suggests
that mental illness can, in a limited and nuanced way, even alter fundamental civic
rights.
Hopper’s comment that reclaiming a lost sense of possibility will require
‘sensitive work’ suggests, however, the danger that Nussbaum and Sen flag concerning
an objective view of human flourishing: the danger of paternalism. If the
central aim of the recovery model is to articulate a conception of a life worth
living which fits the values of the person concerned, but if mental illness can
corrode their sense of possibility and undermine their agency, how can the right
endpoint for healthcare for them be selected without external imposition?
Although highlighted within conceptions of recovery drawn from a capabilities
approach, this general problem seems also to affect the more abstract account
of recovery developed in the previous section. If recovery is aimed at a
conception of flourishing articulated by the mentally ill patient or client him
or herself, and if mental illness can affect his or her ability authentically
to choose, what should guide the right conception of recovery?
In the final two sections of this chapter, I will suggest a role for
narrative in addressing this problem. In the next section I will highlight the
connection between recovery and narrative and draw on one particular view of
narrative for a narrative sense of self. In the final section I will argue that
this helps address the risk of paternalism whichever view of capabilities and whichever
view of autonomy is adopted.
The link to narrative
To begin
the section, I will first motivate the idea that narrative is a helpful place
to address the tension between two different versions of the capabilities-based
approach to recovery. There have been a number of claims that there is a close direct
connection between recovery and narrative understanding. One indication of this
is the proliferation of ‘recovery stories’ as part of the promotion of the recovery
approach. These explore:
the personal and existential dimensions of recovery, taking the
form of subjective and self-evaluated accounts of how an individual has learned
to accommodate to an illness. These accounts have become the founding stories of
the recovery movement [e.g. Chamberlin, 1978; Lovejoy, 1984; Deegan, 1988, 1996;
Leete, 1989; Unzicker, 1989; Clay, 1994; Coleman, 1999; Ridgeway, 2000], and anthologies
of these personal stories have been used by governments and professions as a means
of combating stigma and reasserting a focus on personal perspectives [Leibrich,
1999; Lapsley et al, 2002; Ramsay et al, 2002]. [Roberts and Wolfson 2004: 38-9]
More generally
it is claimed that people who have suffered mental illness can be helped towards
recovery through a narrative based theory. Pat Bracken and Phil Thomas, for example,
cite both Larry Davidson and Glen Roberts.
In their work on recovery, both Davidson and Roberts choose not
to use an approach grounded in traditional descriptive psychopathology, but turn
instead to narrative theory and methods, seeing this as providing a rigorous empirical
and clinical methodology in helping people suffering from chronic psychosis to move
to recovery. [Bracken and Thomas 2009: 245]
On Bracken
and Thomas’ view, clinical work is informed by narrative theory which is distinct
from traditional Jasperian descriptive psychopathology. Roberts himself makes the
connection between recovery and narrative even closer (or at least even more explicit).
By contrast with Bracken and Thomas, he sees a narrative view as consistent with
Jaspers’ view of understanding (by contrast with explanation).
A narrative view values content, and in seeking to understand
delusions and hallucinations, as opposed to explaining them [Jaspers 1974], one
is engaged in re-contextualising the illness in the life experience of the individual.
This in turn may inform the rehabilitation process and give insight into the complexities
of recovery, which for some will include the loss of the compensations of delusional
beliefs and re-engagement with the implications of having a severe mental illness
and what preceded it [Roberts 1999]. [Roberts 2000: 436]
But he goes
on to suggest (or at least to make explicit the idea) that subjects or patients
– rather than only clinicians – possess a narrative understanding and it is this
which can help or hinder them in recovery.
Patients with self-sufficient, unelaborated, dismissive narratives
need to be encouraged to break open their defensive stories and consider other possibilities.
Conversely, those who seem unable to find a narrative thread and to be drowning
in the chaos of their experience need help to find a shape and pattern that enables
them to fit things into place [Holmes, 1999]. In therapy, patients learn to build
up their storytelling capacity, their “autobiographical competence” [Holmes, 1993].
[Roberts 2000: 436]
Across the
literature there is evidence of an idea that narratives structure subjects’ lives
in such a way that partially determines what seems possible to them. Therapists
can propose new life ‘plots’ and help map out new possibilities in the face of mental
illness and hence new possibilities for recovery. To take a non-mental health example,
therapists can propose new plotlines to spinal cord injured patients for whom there
is, sadly, no going back to their past able-bodied plots. They have suffered a kind
of ‘narrative wreckage’ from which they need rescuing in a dialogue with therapists
[Frank 1997: 53-56].
Whilst that
direct connection between narrative understanding and recovery is potentially an
important clinical one, it is not a necessary connection. Exploring the options
for a flourishing life through the idea of stories may in itself be directly therapeutic
for many people, but it is possible that such an approach might fail because, for
example, it may remind people of what they cannot do anymore.
What is the
conceptual or logical connection between a recovery model and narrative understanding?
Narrative theorists who apply the idea of narrative to social phenomena face a strategic
choice. Either, they offer a specific detailed account of narrative in which case
it narrows the range of application of narrative theory since few social phenomena
will fit all the characteristics of narrative so defined. Or, they stress the universal
application of narrative theory and hence are forced to offer a more general, thinner
characterisation of narrative.
In the former
approach, they may, for example, divide narratives into: abstract, orientation,
complicating action, evaluation, resolution and coda [Labov and Waletsky,
1967]. Or, alternatively:
temporality, people, action, certainty (or not) and context [Clandinin and
Connelly 2000]. In practice
there is a great deal of overlap between the accounts. Nevertheless, there is no
obvious necessary connection between a recovery model and narrative understood in
this detailed concrete way. Whilst narratives may often have the elements narrative
theorists favour, and whilst this may contingently be true of the kind of ‘recovery
stories’ often published in support of the recovery approach, there is no need to
link the very idea of recovery in mental healthcare to the provision of a narrative
with all of the parts of a favoured detailed theory of narrative.
But if not, what is the role of narrative understanding and recovery? A more
plausible approach to answer this question is to take a more modest view of the
necessary and sufficient elements of narrative understanding. The philosopher Peter
Goldie articulates just such a minimal account in his last book The Mess Inside [Goldie 2012]. His account
of narrative starts with the general claim that:
A narrative is a representation of events which is shaped, organized,
and coloured, presenting those events, and the people involved in them, from a certain
perspective or perspectives, and thereby giving narrative structure – coherence,
meaningfulness, and evaluative and emotional import – to what is narrated. [Goldie
2012: 8]
This definition emphasises that a narrative is a representation. It
is constructed from the perspective of a narrator even when the narrative is not
actually written or told and is merely an exercise of thought by a subject. Thus
the narrative is fundamentally distinct from what it represents: the events or,
for example, the life of a subject being narrated. The three characteristics of
the structure of the narrative thus pertain to the narrative and not to what is
narrated.
The first
characteristic feature of a narrative is that it has coherence, in the sense that it reveals, through the process
of emplotment, connections between the related events, and it does so in a way that
a mere list, or annal, or chronicle, does not. [ibid: 14]
In fact, Goldie does not attempt to say very much about the nature
of narrative coherence. Surprisingly, given that narrative structure might be thought
to be distinct from the nomological or lawlike structure of the physical sciences,
he uses a comparison with causal explanation. Such explanations cite factors that
are typically neither necessary nor sufficient for the explanans [Mackie 1993].
But they are selected from the total set of causal factors for an event on the basis
of the interests of the author and audience of the account. Although he denies that
there is a simple relation between causal explanation and narrative understanding,
Goldie suggests that this is common with narrative accounts.
A further clue to the nature of narrative coherence comes from a remark
on the epistemological of narrative construction. Borrowing and modifying Paul Ricoeur’s
notion of ‘emplotment’ itself based on Aristotle’s Poetics, Goldie suggests that it involves shaping, organizing, and colouring
events, the raw material of the narrative, itself always already described in significant
ways. Arriving at this is a matter of tâtonnement
or trial and error, feeling one’s way to the real significance of what is narrated.
The process of emplotment is often a tâtonnement, a tentative,
groping procedure: one might begin with an idea of how the narrative should be shaped,
and, once one has developed it somewhat, one might be able to see saliences that
one could not see before, and then find it appropriate to go back and reshape the
narrative in this new light. More than that, the tâtonnement typically involves
a groping search for the appropriate evaluative and emotional import of what is
narrated. [ibid: 11]
The second general characteristic set out is meaningfulness. Goldie
suggests that there are two aspects to the meaning of narratives.
First, a narrative can be meaningful by revealing how the thoughts,
feelings, and actions of those people who are internal to the narrative could have
made sense of them from their perspective at the time—that is, from their internal perspective. And, secondly,
a narrative can be meaningful by revealing the narrator’s external perspective: his or her thoughts and feelings
that throw light on why the narrative was related (or just thought through) in that
particular way. Bound up with these two kinds of meaningfulness are the two ways
in which a narrative can have evaluative and emotional import. [ibid: 17]
This connects to the third key element: the evaluative and emotional
import of narratives. In a nutshell.
Things matter to people, and a narrative involving people can
capture the way things matter to them. [ibid: 23]
These characteristics are supposed to apply across the board to narratives.
Goldie has, however, a particular focus: autobiographical narrative thinking. In
particular, he discusses in depth autobiographical thinking about one’s past and
one’s future. Both illustrate the claim that an autobiographical narrative sense
of self is an essential aspect of human subjectivity.
In the case of narrative thinking about the past, the difference between
internal and external perspective on both meaning and evaluative and emotional import
plays a role. In thinking, now, about one’s past, an autobiographical narrative
presents a view of the meaning and significance of past events and actions through
the emotional lens of the present. A mismatch between past and present perspectives
can take the form of regret in cases where one realises that had one not acted in
such and such a way, such an effect would not have occurred.
In narrative thinking about the future, imagination plays a role analogous
to memory in thinking about the past. Goldie suggests that it plays a key role in
thinking through the ‘branching possibilities’ of different ways in which events
may come to pass. In future directed thinking, there is again a difference between
internal and external perspective on both meaning and evaluative and emotional import.
One can imagine not only different future actions but also their emotional effects.
The emotion imagined for the future can have an emotional effect in the present.
Goldie suggests that narrative thinking is also involved in developing virtues.
One connection is through fictional narratives. An emotional response to the lives
and actions of fictional characters enables an understanding goes had in hand with
an imagined response to other possibilities. But the same applies to future planning
for one’s own life based on responses of shame and guilt to mistakes made in the
past and hence the adoption of counter-factual and causal thinking about how to
act in the future.
Narrative, paternalism and
Hopper’s ‘sensitive wok’
Kim Hopper’s mention (above) of the ‘sensitive work’ needed to
recover a suppressed sense of injustice and reclaim lost possibility reflects
the dual dilemma for a clinician of either paternalistically imposing an
entirely external view of what someone in recovery from mental illness ought to
want or failing to challenge a view which may be impoverished by mental
illness, stigma and even, in some cases, experience of psychiatric treatment. If
the central aim of the recovery model is to articulate a conception of a life
worth living which fits the values of the person concerned, but if mental
illness can corrode their sense of possibility and undermine their agency, how
can the right endpoint for healthcare for them be selected?
Although it does not offer a way out of the fundamental tension
articulated by Nussbaum and Sen, a narrative sense of self offers some
practical help. Narrative, understood along the lines that Goldie suggests, has
a balance of subjectivity and objectivity. The objectivity lies in the need for
narrative coherence and structure and in the implicit contrast between internal
and external perspectives in narratives. The subjectivity lies in the essentially
perspectival nature of the narratives. Autobiographical narratives are both
narrated from a particular perspective but also concern the life of the very
same person as the narrator. These come together in the tâtonnement, the tentative,
reaching for the right narrative structure of events.
On a broadly procedural view of autonomy, any intervention to
impose values on a subject who already enjoys a reflective balance between
first and second order values and policies is a form of paternalism. But there
may still be a need for what Hopper calls ‘sensitive work’ is a subject’s self
narrative is incoherent. For example, is there is a lack of coherence between
past regret and suitable future directed policies to avoid similar errors in
the future. Clinical narrative-based intervention could take the form of working
with a client to enable their understanding of their past and plans for the
future to fit their current conception of themselves. Narrative self-understanding
introduces a temporal dimension and the explicit possibility of divergence of
value between what one valued in the past, values now and may come to value in
the future. Narrative coherence provides a standard by which present values and
habits can be subject to criticism by the subject her or himself. In the initial
apparent dilemma, an extreme of relativism is avoided insofar as a conception
of flourishing and hence recovery will have to have a form of narrative
coherence for the subject. Whilst the notion of objectivity within narrative
understanding is not one of external
On a substantive view of autonomy, answering to external,
universal standards for human flourishing need not involve paternalism. Hence a
clinician’s ‘sensitive work’ may involve persuasion that some forms of life are
more valuable than others and their neglect by a subject is the result of his
or her illness. Whilst external standards need not seem to a substantivist to
threaten paternalism they could. Given the connection, to which both sides of
the debate about capabilities agree, between flourishing and freedom a brute
imposition of an external view of flourishing could be paternalistic. But if externally
proffered conceptions of the good life are suggested and adopted as part of a
narratively structured set of policies and plans for future life reconciled
with the subject’s narrative account of their past and present too then that is
not a brute imposition. Even if a clinician has to work to introduce neglected
values, if they are adopted they will have to made to cohere by the subject him
or herself with a narrative account. This avoids the charge of crude
paternalism.
Emphasising the normative standards implicit in the idea of
narrative coherence is not a quick fix for a balanced conception of recovery.
The severely depressed person quoted by Ratcliffe (above) was, at the time of
the experiences described, incapable of the kind of narrative understanding
just outlined. In such cases, a recovery model can neither be adopted nor can
it coherently be imposed. But a narrative sense of self suggests a rationale
for a middle way between paternalism and uncritical relativism whichever broad
view of recovery and of autonomy is adopted.
Conclusion
In
this chapter I have attempted to shed light on three related issues. First, in the light of its recent popularity and promotion as the goal of mental healthcare, what is meant by 'recovery'? Second, how can the harm that mental illness can do to people's autonomy be reconciled with a recovery approach which is based on patient or client choice? Third, does the existing connection between recovery and narrative shed light on the first two issues?
Drawing
on typical statements of the aims of the recovery movement in mental healthcare, I have articulated an abstract specification for a recovery model. It is health rather than illness based and it is essentially value laden. Recovery aims towards the goal of a conception of flourishing tailor-made to individual patients and clients. This is consistent with one elaboration of a theory of recovery based on Sen's capabilities approach to welfare economics. On that model, the valued 'functionings' that underpin capability are person-specific. But as two of the key architects of that policy suggest, there is a tension between two rival versions of it. On one (Nussbaum's), there are universal standards for human flourishing. On the other (Sen's), the emphasis on freedom as a key aspect of capability implies diversity. These two views give rise to two opposing perceived dangers: uncritical relativism versus paternalism.
Paternalism
is a threat to human autonomy and the two approaches to capabilities correspond to two broad approaches to it. On a proceduralist account, autonomy is a form of internal coherence of beliefs and values. On a substantivist account, the idea of autonomy presupposes successfully tracking some particular conception of the good and the true.
The
two view find expression within recovery on a stress on human diversity (Davidson) versus the idea of some universal standards coupled with the idea that mental illness may cloud people's judgements of flourishing so understood or otherwise undermine their agency (Hopper). This raises a threat, however, that in responding to this clinicians will inevitably be paternalist.
On
the assumption that mental illness can indeed distort people's views of their own flourishing, the final section has suggested that a narrative sense of
self can play a role in undermining the threat of paternalism. On a proceduralist view of autonomy, and Sen's version of capabilities, a clouding of judgement is a lack of coherence in a narrative sense of self and hence the sensitive work to correct this involves helping the patient or client to repair their own narrative. On a substantive view of autonomy, which corresponds to Nussbaum's view of capabilities, a clouding of judgement may also involve failing to observe universal forms of human flourishing. And hence the sensitive work to correct this involves enabling a patient to see the rightness of these universal forms. But the role of narrative ensures that this is not a brute imposition from without. Only if the subject can integrate the universal values into his or her own narrative will the work have been successful.
Bibliography
Boorse, C. (1975)
‘On the distinction between disease and illness’ Philosophy and Public Affairs 5: 49-68
Bracken, P. and Thomas, P. (2009) ‘Authors’ response. Invited
commentary on… Beyond consultation’ Psychiatric
Bulletin 33: 245-246
Brampton,
S. (2008) Shoot the Damn Dog: A Memoir of
Depression. London:
Bloomsbury
Brown, W. and Kandirikirira, N (2007). Recovering mental health
in Scotland. Report on narrative investigation of mental health recovery.
Glasgow, Scottish Recovery Network
Chamberlin, J. (1978)
On Our Own: Patient Controlled Alternatives
to the Mental Health System, New York: McGraw-Hill
Clandinin DJ & Connelly FM (2000) Narrative Inquiry: Experience
and Story in Qualitative Research. Jossey-Bass, San Francisco, CA.
Clay, S. (1994) The wounded prophet. In Recovery: The New Force
in Mental Health, Columbus, OH: Ohio Department of Mental Health
Coleman, R. (1999)
Recovery: An Alien Concept, Gloucester:
Hansell Publishing
Corrigan, P.W. and Watson, A.C. (2002) ‘The Paradox of
Self-Stigma and Mental Illness’ Clinical
Psychology: Science and Practice 9: 35–53
Davidson, L. and Roe,
D. (2007) ‘Recovery from recovery in serious mental illness: one strategy for lessening
confusion plaguing recovery’ Journal of Mental
Health 16: 459-470.
Davidson,
L., Ridgway, P., Wieland, M., & O'Connell, M. (2009). A capabilities
approach to mental health transformation: a conceptual framework for the
recovery era. Canadian Journal of Community Mental Health (Revue canadienne de santé
mentale communautaire), 28(2), 35-46
Deegan, P. E. (1988)
‘Recovery: the lived experience of rehabilitation’ Psychosocial Rehabilitation Journal, 11: 11-19
Deegan, P. (1996)
‘Recovery as a journey of the heart’ Psychiatric
Rehabilitation Journal 19: 91-97
Frank, A.W.
(1997) The Wounded Storyteller,
Chicago: University of Chicago Press
Frankfurt, H. (1971) ‘Freedom of the Will and the Concept of the
Person’ Journal of Philosophy
Fulford, K.W.M. (1989)
Moral Theory and Medical Practice, Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press
Goldie, P. (2012) The Mess Inside: narrative, emotion, and the mind, Oxford: Oxford
University Press
Holmes, J. (1993) John Bowlby and Attachment Theory.
London: Routledge
Holmes, J. (1999) ‘Defensive and creative uses of narrative
in psychotherapy’ In Healing Stories: Narrative in Psychiatry and Psychotherapy
(eds G. Roberts & J. Holmes) pp. 152–180. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Hopper,
K. (2007) Rethinking social recovery in schizophrenia: what a capabilities
approach might offer. Social Science & Medicine 65: 868-879
Jaspers, K. ([1913] 1974) ‘Causal and “Meaningful” Connections
between Life History and Psychosis’, trans. by J.Hoenig, in S.R.Hirsch and
M.Shepherd. in Hirsch, S.R., and M. Shepherd, Themes and Variations in European Psychiatry, Bristol: Wright: 80-93
Kendell, R.E. (1975)
‘The concept of disease and its implications for psychiatry’ British Journal of Psychiatry 127: 305-315
Labov, W. and Waletsky, J. (1967) Narrative analysis, in J. Helm (ed)
Essays on the Verbal and Visual Arts.
Seattle: University of Washington Press.
Lapsley, H., Waimarie,
L. N. & Black, R. (2002) Kia Mauri Tau!
Narratives of Recovery from Disabling Mental Health Problems, Wellington: Mental
Health Commission
Leete, E. (1989) ‘How
I perceive and manage my illness’ Schizophrenia Bulletin, 8: 605-609
Leibrich, J. (1999)
A Gift of Stories: Discovering How to Deal
with Mental Illness, Dunedin: University of Otago Press
Lovejoy, M. (1984)
‘Recovery from schizophrenia: a personal Odyssey’ Hospital and Community Psychiatry, 35: 809-812
Mackie, J.L. (1993) ‘Causes and conditionals’
in Sosa, E. and Tooley, M. (eds) Causation,
Oxford: Oxford University Press: 33-50
Nussbaum, M. (1988). ‘Nature, Function, and Capability: Aristotle
on Political Distribution’, Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy, suppl.
vol.
Nussbaum, M. and Sen, A. (eds) (1993) The Quality of Life, Oxford: Clarendon
Ramsay, R., Page, A., Goodman, T., et al (2002) Changing Minds: Our Lives and Mental Illness,
London: Gaskell
Ratcliffe, M.R. (2015) Experiences of Depression: a study in phenomenology, Oxford: Oxford
University Press
Ridgeway, P. A. (2000) ‘Re-storying psychiatric disability:
learning from first person narrative accounts of recovery’ Psychiatric Rehabilitation Journal 24: 335-343
Roberts, G. (1999) ‘The rehabilitation of rehabilitation:
a narrative approach to psychosis’ In Healing Stories: Narrative in Psychiatry
and Psychotherapy (eds G .Roberts & J. Holmes), pp. 152-180. Oxford: Oxford
University Press.
Roberts, G. (2000) ‘Narrative and severe mental illness: what place
do stories have in an evidence-based world?’ Advances
in Psychiatric Treatment 6: 432-441
Roberts, G. and Wolfson, P. (2004) ‘The rediscovery of recovery: open to all’ Advances in Psychiatric Treatment 10: 37-49
Sen, A., 1980, ‘Equality
of What?’ in McMurrin (ed.), Tanner
Lectures on Human Values, Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press.
Sen, A.
(1993) ‘Capability and Well-Being’ in Nussbaum, M. and Sen, A. (eds.) The
Quality of Life, New York: Oxford Clarendon Press
Shepherd, G., Boardman, J. & Slade, M. (2008) Making Recovery a Reality
London: Sainsbury Centre for Mental Health
Szasz, T. (1972) The Myth
of Mental Illness, London: Paladin
Unzicker,
R. (1989) ‘On my own: a personal journey through madness and re-emergence’ Psychosocial Rehabilitation Journal 13: 70-77
Wolf, S. (1990) Freedom within
Reason Oxford: Oxford University Press