McDowell stresses the parallels
between his account of intention in action and the account of perception in Mind and World. In both there is a
central role to the idea of something – an experience or an action – being permeated
with rationality and conceptual structure.
This view has, however, been subject to sustained criticism from
a specifically phenomenological perspective in a number of papers, following
his American Philosophical Association presidential address in 2005, by Hubert
Dreyfus which collectively form a dialogue with McDowell’s various replies [Dreyfus
2005, 2007a, 2007b, 2013; McDowell 2007a, 2007b, 2013]. Dreyfus accuses
McDowell of subscribing to a Myth of the Mental, or, later, refined to a Myth
of the Pervasiveness of the Mental in his, McDowell’s, attempt to reject the
Myth of the Given. McDowell replies in kind by accusing Dreyfus of falling prey
to a Myth of the Mind as Detached.
Dreyfus’ initial criticism stems from a summary of McDowell that
runs as follows.
To suggest how impingements received
from nature can be conceptual through and through without the mind imposing
meaning on a meaningless Given, McDowell introduces an account of Aristotle’s
idea of second nature:
Human beings are...initiated into...the space of reasons by ethical upbringing, which instils the appropriate shape into their lives. The resulting habits of thought and action are second nature. [McDowell 1994: 84]
McDowell then generalizes Aristotle’s account of the production of second nature:
[i]mposing a specific shape on the practical intellect, is a particular case of a general phenomenon: initiation into conceptual capacities, which include responsiveness to other rational demands besides those of ethics. [ibid: 84]
The phenomenon McDowell has in mind is clearest in phronesis, usually translated ‘practical wisdom’. [Dreyfus 2005: 50]
Human beings are...initiated into...the space of reasons by ethical upbringing, which instils the appropriate shape into their lives. The resulting habits of thought and action are second nature. [McDowell 1994: 84]
McDowell then generalizes Aristotle’s account of the production of second nature:
[i]mposing a specific shape on the practical intellect, is a particular case of a general phenomenon: initiation into conceptual capacities, which include responsiveness to other rational demands besides those of ethics. [ibid: 84]
The phenomenon McDowell has in mind is clearest in phronesis, usually translated ‘practical wisdom’. [Dreyfus 2005: 50]
Dreyfus agrees
that phronesis is a paradigm case of
human perception and action. But he suggests that, on a proper understanding of
it, it cannot fit McDowell’s conceptualised account. In the exercise of phronesis
or practical wisdom in making ethical judgements, for example, one simply sees what to do, without deliberation.
As Aristotle says: Phronesis…
involves knowledge of the ultimate particular thing, which cannot be attained
by systematic knowledge but only by ‘perception’… Aristotle’s account of phronesis
does not assume, as McDowell does, that, ethical expertise can be
conceptually articulated. On the contrary, phronesis shows that
socialization can produce a kind of master whose actions do not rely on habits
based on reasons to guide him. Indeed, thanks to socialization, a person’s
perceptions and actions at their best would be so responsive to the specific
situation that they could not be captured in general concepts. [Dreyfus 2005:
51]
Instead, Dreyfus suggests that phronesis is an instance of
skilled, embodied coping which runs counter to what he takes to be McDowell’s
commitment to detached, conceptually articulated rule following. Furthermore,
he suggests that McDowell’s claim that perception is conceptual runs counter to
the fact that we share perceptual capacities with prelinguistic infants and
animals and that he cannot account for how the ‘ground floor of pure perception
and receptive coping supports the conceptual upper stories of the edifice of
knowledge’ [Dreyfus 2005: 61].
McDowell summarises the challenge that Dreyfus raises as centring
on how the existence of apparently nonconceptual embodied coping can be
reconciled with McDowell’s claims about there being nothing beyond the limits
of the conceptual.
It would follow that if conceptual
rationality is everywhere, there is no room anywhere for embodied coping
skills. And our perceptual experience needs to be understood in the context of
our embodied coping skills. But why should we accept that embodied coping
skills are, just as such, nonconceptual? [McDowell 2007a: 339]
In his first reply to Dreyfus in the paper ‘What myth?’, McDowell
offers three responses [McDowell 2007a].
·
reasons can be situation specific
·
one can acquire new conceptual capacities from
particular situations
·
there can be continuity with animals
First, McDowell denies that his account of either Aristotle’s
phronesis, or of ethical judgement more generally, can be couched in
situation-independent terms.
I reject the idea that the content of
practical wisdom, as Aristotle understands it, can be captured in general
prescriptions for conduct, determinately expressible independently of the
concrete situations in which the phronimos [the subject or agent possessing
phronesis] is called on to act. [McDowell 2007a: 340]
McDowell concedes that, in a passage of his that Dreyfus quotes,
he describes phronesis as involving ‘habits of thought and action’. And he
concedes that ‘habit’ implies some sort of generality. But (as described in
chapter 2, above) this does not imply that practical wisdom can be encoded in
situation-independent, general terms.
But conceiving phronesis as a habit, or
a set of habits, is consistent with holding that the only way one can register
the generality of phronesis is by a description on these lines: ‘the habit of
responding to situations as phronesis requires’. And that leaves what response
a particular situation calls for from the phronimos still needing to be
determined by situation-specific discernment. [McDowell 2007a: 341
In other words, he denies the forced choice between either situation-independent,
general and conceptual judgement or situation-dependent and nonconceptual
coping. As a paradigm of human perception and action, phronesis can be both
situation-dependent and nevertheless a conceptually structured ability. For
rational subjects such as mature human beings, ‘embodied coping is permeated
with mindedness’ [McDowell 2007a: 339].
Second, in line with this, and with the idea mentioned above that
perceptual experience needs to be understood in the context of embodied coping
skills, McDowell offers the following thumbnail sketch of the perceptual
experience of a rational subject:
[I]f an experience is world-disclosing,
which implies that it is categorially unified, all its content is present in a
form in which, as I put it before, it is suitable to constitute contents of
conceptual capacities. All that would be needed for a bit of it to come to
constitute the content of a conceptual capacity, if it is not already the
content of a conceptual capacity, is for it to be focused on and made to be the
meaning of a linguistic expression. [McDowell 2007a: 346]
This reflects the account in Mind
and World of demonstrative concepts (described in chapter 5, above). It
disarms the objection that perceptual content cannot be conceptually structured
because it is too fine grained. Instead, concepts can be as fine grained as
perceptual discriminations allow.
Third, he attempts to disarm Dreyfus’ objection that because
perceptual capacities are shared with prelinguistic infants and non-linguistic animals
they cannot be conceptually structured.
The claim that the capacities and skills
are shared comes to no more than this: there are descriptions of things we can
do that apply also to things other animals can do. For instance: any
animal—rational or not— with suitable sensory equipment, engaged in getting
from one place to another, can be expected, other things being equal, to
respond to the affordance constituted by a sufficiently large opening, in a
wall that otherwise blocks its path, by going through the opening. But the
truth about a human being’s exercise of competence in making her way around, in
a performance that can be described like that, need not be exhausted by the
match with what can be said about, say, a cat’s correspondingly describable response
to a corresponding affordance. The human being’s response is, if you like,
indistinguishable from the cat’s response qua response to an affordance
describable in those terms. But it does not follow that the human being’s
response cannot be unlike the cat’s response in being the human being’s
rationality at work. [McDowell 2007a: 343]
This, again, fits an idea in Mind
and World but also in the paper ‘One strand in the private language
argument’ (discussed in chapter 1) that there can be conceptual and
non-conceptual species variants of the same genus.
In his reply to McDowell’s paper ‘What myth?’, Dreyfus concedes
that he had wrongly assumed that McDowell understood rationality and
conceptuality to be general in the sense of situation-independent and hence assumed
that McDowell could not think of phronesis as situation-specific skilful
coping. Nevertheless, he argues that:
McDowell’s view that ‘in mature human
beings, embodied coping is permeated with mindedness’, suggests a new version
of the mentalist myth which, like the others, is untrue to the phenomenon….
Where I differ from McDowell is that I hold that situation-specific mindedness,
far from being a pervasive and essential feature of human being, is the result
of a specific transformation of our pervasive mindless absorbed coping.
[Dreyfus 2007a: 355]
According to Dreyfus, mindedness – whether tied to specific
situations or not – is based on a form of skilled, absorbed coping which is
itself mindless. Further, mindedness is a mark of mere competence. Mastery, by
contrast, requires the retreat of explicit guidelines, rules and even reasons
to leave a form of coping that is nonconceptual and nonminded.
When we are following the advice of a
coach, for example, our behavior regresses to mere competence. It is only after
much practice, and after abandoning monitoring and letting ourselves be drawn
back into full involvement in our activity, that we can regain our expertise.
The resulting expert coping returns to being direct and unreflective, which I
take to be the same as being nonconceptual and nonminded. [Dreyfus 2007a: 355]
Thus, phenomenology suggests that,
although many forms of expertise pass through a stage in which one needs
reasons to guide action, after much involved experience, the learner develops a
way of coping in which reasons play no role. [Dreyfus 2005: 53]
To highlight the incompatibility he sees between the expertise
and the exercise of conceptual rationality, he gives the example of the
baseball player Chuck Knoblauch who turned from being a masterful player when
relying on absorbed skilled coping to being a bad player when he tried to
follow explicit procedures for catching and throwing the ball.
As second baseman for the New York
Yankees, Knoblauch was so successful he was voted best infielder of the year,
but one day, rather than simply fielding a hit and throwing the ball to first
base, it seems he stepped back and took up a ‘free, distanced orientation’
towards the ball and how he was throwing it — to the mechanics of it, as he put
it. After that, he couldn’t recover his former absorption and often—though not
always — threw the ball to first base erratically — once into the face of a
spectator. [Dreyfus 2007a: 354]
The point of the example is supposed to be that Knoblauch turned
from being a Dreyfusian agent to a McDowellian agent, from someone who can
engage in masterful nonconceptual mindless activity to conceptually structured
acting for reasons but now hopelessly distanced from the game and his prior
skill. Since Knoblauch is obviously exceptional and since skilled performance
is possible, then McDowell’s account cannot be generally true or so runs Dreyfus’
implication. But such an example relies on an assumption that McDowell rejects:
that a mindful or conceptually articulated response must be a reflective
exercise of disengaged ratiocination.
McDowell accepts the transcendental
argument that the conditions of the possibility of the mind relating its
content to the world requires conceptual capacities, and these capacities must always be everywhere operative in
human experience. Phenomenologists, on the contrary, contend that this argument
is based on the phenomenologically unjustified assumption that we are basically
minds distanced from the world, so that the mind has to be related to the world
by mental activity, whereas, when one is fully absorbed in coping the
mind/world dichotomy disappears. The assumption that there is an essential
distance between mind and world that must be bridged by concepts, thoughts, and
reasons is what I have been calling the Myth of the Pervasiveness of the
Mental. [Dreyfus 2013: 36]
In this passage, Dreyfus connects together the idea of conceptual
activity with distance from the world and hence a need to bridge the gap
between mind and world with concepts, thoughts, and reasons. But whether or not
McDowell’s account of perceptual experience and action is, in the end,
plausible, Dreyfus seems simply to ignore, rather than argue against, a key
element of McDowell’s picture. Specifically, whilst action is sometimes the result of the formation of a prior
intention, or intention for the future, through a reflective and deliberative
exercise of practical reasoning, it need not be. It can be a spontaneous
response to the situation.
Further, extending O’Shaughnessy’s
dual aspect account of willing discussed in the first part of this chapter,
McDowell stresses the idea that the action itself just is the intention in
action when construed mentally. The action is not distinct from the exercise of
conceptual capacities. Intentions do not merely instigate actions from outside the ‘precincts of action’ (in O’Shaughnessy’s phrase)
in the way that an intention to topple a tree may take the form of sawing
through the trunk with the expectation that that will lead, causally to the
tree’s toppling. Intention can be present in the action of crossing the road,
for example. So Dreyfus’ assumption that when McDowell claims that actions and perceptual
experiences must be conceptual then that introduces an essential gap between
mind and world should sound alarm bells. McDowell’s explicit aim is precisely
the opposite. The claim that experiences are conceptually structured is
supposed to show how it can be the case that experience is a form of direct
openness to the world. Actions are supposed to be directly expressive of
conceptual ability, not its action at a distance. If a gap is introduced by either
of these claims about conceptual structure then Dreyfus needs to show why that
is the case rather than simply assume it.
McDowell considers the case of a woman who, whilst walking across
a park, spontaneously catches a Frisbee as it flies towards her.
When a rational agent catches a frisbee,
she is realizing a concept of a thing to do. In the case of a skilled agent,
she does not do that by realizing other concepts of things to do. She does not
realize concepts of contributory things to do, in play for her as concepts of
what she is to do by virtue of her means-end rationality in a context in which
her overarching project is to catch the frisbee. But she does realize a concept
of, say, catching this… The point of saying that the rational agent, unlike the
dog, is realizing a concept in doing what she does is that her doing, under a
specification that captures the content of the practical concept that she is
realizing, comes within the scope of her practical rationality — even if only
in that, if asked why she caught the frisbee, she would answer ‘No particular
reason; I just felt like it’. [McDowell 2007b: 369]
Elsewhere, he calls the prospective answer a ‘limiting case of
practical rationality at work’ and a ‘null response’ [McDowell 2013: 49]. This
because whilst such a response does not reject the ‘why?’ question that
Anscombe claims marks out the intentional realm it does report that there is no
informative or interesting answer as to why catching a frisbee was thought to
be a good idea, no further, distinct purpose behind it, no broader further structure
of means-end rationality [Anscombe 2000: 84-5]. But it does accept the
attribution of intentionality. It accepts ‘catching the frisbee’ as a correct
description of the intentional action and hence as a reason for what she did
in, for example, stretching out her arm. The details of her motor-intentionality
are, as described earlier, the shape taken by her intention in action as it
becomes determined.
Dreyfus offers his example of someone acting without deliberation
and in flow. In lightning chess, the whole game has to be played in less than
two minutes. Hence grandmasters must make moves as fast as they can move their
arms and yet are still able to play with great expertise.
Fortunately, the expert usually does not
need to calculate. If he has had enough experience and stays involved, he will
find himself responding in a masterful way before he has time to think. Just as
Aristotle, Heidegger, and Merleau-Ponty saw, such mastery requires a rich
perceptual repertoire — the ability to respond to subtle differences in the
appearance of perhaps hundreds of thousands of situations — but it requires no
conceptual repertoire at all. This holds true for such refined skills as chess,
jazz improvisation, sports, martial arts, etc., but also for everyday skills
such as cooking dinner, crossing a busy street, carrying on a conversation, or
just getting around in the world. [Dreyfus 2005: 58]
Returning to this example more recently, he runs the case of
lightning chess and the Frisbee catcher together:
The woman’s inability to provide a
rational motivation and the master’s
inability to provide a rational explanation
of why a certain move worked are examples of the limitation of rationality. In
both cases rationality is not pervasive. [Dreyfus 2013: 35]
He goes on to distinguish them in that frisbee catcher is a ‘genuine
null case’ because she cannot give an account of her account even though, he
suggests, she should. By contrast in the lightnight chess player’s case there
is a ‘positive absence of a reason’ where the lack of a reason is not
disturbing but a sign of a more direct response to the possibilities of moves
suggested by the configuration of the chess board.
This first account seems to distort the phenomenology. Not every
act needs to be embedded in a hierarchy of further reasons. And not being so embedded
does not mean that, as a deliberate if spontaneous act, it is not an expression
of the agent’s rationality. On McDowell’s picture, the fisbee catcher is
realising a concept practically which she could, given time, put into the words
that describe both action and intention in action: “I am catching this”. There is
no need for embarrassment that there is no further reason than that she wished to.
The chess master, by contrast, expresses a non-limiting and
non-null form of rationality. Given time, though not when in flow, he can
answer a question as to why he did what he did. Dreyfus argues, to the
contrary, that he is merely mindlessly and non-conceptually responding to the
forces of the pieces on the chess board. But as McDowell points out, even if
all he can say is, somewhat abstractly, that he is responding to them, then
that is sufficient to show his is not a limiting or null case. The exercise of
conceptual rationality that would be expressed in a reconstruction, after the
fact, of his thinking is also expressed practically when acting, rapidly and in
flow, in response to the different configurations of pieces. And as McDowell
argues:
[I]f he really is a master, it must be
within his powers to be more specific. We can expect him to be able to say such
things as this: ‘It’s a good move because, it threatens my opponent’s queen’…
[W]e cannot compel him to talk about his move without breaking the flow. But…
that does not matter. He will be saying things he already knew whilst acting in
flow. [McDowell 2013: 47]
Both the chess master and the frisbee catcher are able to do
something that Chuck Knoblauch could not do. This suggests an aspect of the
phenomenology of absorbed coping: that it is incompatible with simultaneously
taking a more distanced and reflective view. But on McDowell’s view, the same
conceptual understanding is in play in these two different ways. Dreyfus offers
no compelling argument against the claim that conceptual abilities are manifested
in both experience and action, even if the mark of this is not an occurrent phenomenon
at the time but a standing ability or power to take part in the game of giving
and asking for reasons.
References
Anscombe, E. (2000) Intention, Cambridge,Mass.: Harvard
University Press
Brandom, R. (1994) Making It Explicit: Reasoning, Representing,
and Discursive Commitment. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press
Davidson, D. (1980) Essays on
Actions and Events, Oxford: Oxford University Press
Dreyfus, H. (2005) ‘Overcoming the
Myth of the Mental: How Philosophers Can Profit from the Phenomenology of
Everyday Expertise’ Proceedings and
Addresses of the American Philosophical Association, 79: 47-65
Dreyfus, H. (2007a) ‘The Return of the Myth of the Mental’. Inquiry 50, 4: 352–365.
Dreyfus, H. (2007b) ‘Response to McDowell’. Inquiry
50, 4: 371–377.
Dreyfus, H. (2013) ‘The myth of the pervasiveness of the mental’ in
Schear, J.K. (ed) Mind, Reason, and
Being-in-the-World, London: Routledge pp15-40
Haddock, A. (2011) ‘The knowledge that a man has of his intentional
actions’ in Ford, A., Hornsby, J. & Stoutland, F. (eds.) Essays on Anscombe’s Intention, Cambridge,
MA.: Harvard University Press pp147-69
McDowell, J. (1994) Mind
and World, Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press
McDowell, J (2007a) ‘What Myth?’ Inquiry 50: 338–351.
McDowell, J.
(2007b) ‘Response to Dreyfus’ Inquiry,
50: 366-370
McDowell, J. (2010) ‘What is the content
of an intention in action?’ Ratio 23: 415-432.
McDowell, J. (2011) ‘Some remarks
on intention in action’ Amherst Lecture in Philosophy. http://www.amherstlecture.org/mcdowell2011/index.html
(accessed January 2, 2012).
McDowell, J. (2013) ‘The myth of mind as detached’ in Schear,
J.K. (ed) Mind, Reason, and
Being-in-the-World, London: Routledge pp41-58
O’Shaughnessy, B. (1991) ‘Searle’s Theory of Action’ in Lepore,
E. and Van Gulick, R. (eds) John Searle
and His Critics, Cambridge, MA, and Oxford: Blackwell pp
O’Shaughnessy, B. (2003) ‘The Epistemology of Physical Action’ in
Johannes Roessler, J. and Eilan, N (eds) Agency
and Self-Awareness, Oxford: Clarendon Press pp345-57
Searle, J. (1983) Intentionality.
New York: Cambridge University Press
Stoutland, F. (2011) ‘Introduction: Anscombe’s Intention in
Context’ in Ford, A., Hornsby, J. & Stoutland, F. (eds.) Essays on Anscombe’s Intention, Cambridge,
Mass.: Harvard University Press pp1-22
Tanney, J. (2013) Rules,
Reason and Self Knowledge, Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press
Thompson, M. (2008) Life
and Action: Elementary Structures of Practice and Practical Thought, Cambridge,
Mass.: Harvard University Press pp147-69
Thompson, M. (2011) ‘Anscombe’s Intention and Practical Knowledge’
in Ford, A., Hornsby, J. & Stoutland, F. (eds.) Essays on Anscombe’s Intention, Cambridge, MA.: Harvard University
Press pp198-210
Wilson, G. M. (1989) The Intentionality of Human Action.
Stanford: Stanford University Press