This is a reworked first section of a chapter for a nursing
textbook. I am trying to say something general about knowledge without
stumbling into an account of the last 50 years of anglo-american epistemology.
This version mentions Gettier’s criticism of the traditional model of knowledge (as justified true belief) but
does not draw the obvious conclusion (that the JTB analysis is false). In the context, I hope this works, is not too misleading.
The value of knowledge
Why should nurses aim to have knowledge
of their subject? What is the value
of knowledge?
Exercise: Think about
this question before reading on. One clue might be to think about possible
opposites to knowledge. If nursing practices were not based on knowledge, on
what might they be based? Write down some ideas.
Answering the question of the value of knowledge is difficult. We
will approach it in this section via a preliminary question: what is knowledge or
what does ‘knowledge’ mean? Now there might not
be a very helpful or informative answer to this question. Imagine that someone asks
what stickiness is or what the word ‘sticky’
means. One might reply by offering a word that means more or less the same: such
as ‘tacky’. But this does not help explain the concept of stickiness so much as
swap one word for it for another. Alternatively, one might offer a more substantial
explanation of the concept such as ‘a tendency of a body to adhere to another on
contact’. Such an explanation may more or less equate to the concept but it isn’t
obvious that a speaker who understands the word ‘sticky’ should be able to offer
such a formal paraphrase nor that hearing the formal paraphrase will teach the
meaning of sticky since it raises further questions such as what the word ‘adhere’
means. But despite these difficulties in defining it, there is generally no
difficulty in learning, understanding and teaching how to apply the word
‘sticky’. So we should approach the question of what knowledge in general is with
some caution. There may not be a very helpful definition available.
Some general features of knowledge can, however, be learnt from particular
examples. Suppose that Sandy knows that, because it is 5pm, Mr Smith is due for medication. If so, she must hold it to be, or take it
to be, true that it is time for his medication. That is, she must at least believe it. (‘At least’ because we often
use the word ‘believe’ when we are not
sure we do know something. “Do you know that?” “Well I believe it.”) Second, if Sandy does know that Mr Smith is due for medication,
then he must really be due for medication. If
she has knowledge, what she believes must
be true.
Third, her belief cannot merely be accidentally true. Suppose Sandy
believes that it is time for Mr Smith’s medication because she knows that he
takes medication every day at 5pm and she believes that it is now 5pm. But
suppose her belief about the time is based on the normally reliable ward clock which
has, in fact, stopped the day before. By chance, however, it is now nearly 5pm.
If so, although Sandy has a true belief about the need, now, for Mr Smith’s medication
she does not know it. Her belief is
merely true by luck. (Earlier in the day she would have formed the false belief
that it was 5pm.) Being lucky will make no difference to how things seem to her
(since she does not realise the clock has stopped) but an observer might say
that she didn’t know the time, she
was right only by luck.
These constraints on knowledge have motivated a definition which dates
back 2,000 years to the Greek philosopher Plato: knowledge is justified, true belief.
The idea is that needing a justification for a belief (for it to count as
knowledge) should rule out merely lucky true beliefs. But this prompts a
question: in the example of Sandy and the stopped ward clock, does that work?
Exercise: Think about this
question for a moment. Does the traditional analysis give the correct account
of Sandy? Here is a clue: ask whether Sandy has a justification for thinking
the time is 5pm and also ask whether her true belief is lucky. If the answer to
both is ‘yes’ then the traditional account does not address the problem of
luck. If it does not, could some modification could be made to the definition?
As well as trying to rule out merely lucky true beliefs, justification
also plays a second role which is relevant for thinking about the challenge of
generating nursing knowledge. It provides a way or a method, or a route, to aim
at true beliefs. It is one thing to worry that one’s beliefs about the latest
medication for mental illness may not be correct, but quite another to work out
how to avoid error.
Suppose some hospital authority issued an instruction that all
nursing staff should replace any false beliefs they hold with true beliefs. On
the face of it, this seems a good aim. But would the instruction help? Could
one act on it? The problem is that ‘from the inside’ true beliefs and false
beliefs seem the same. To hold a belief is to hold it to be true. (To believe that
something is not true is precisely not to believe it.) Thus beliefs which are, in
fact, false are not transparently so to someone who holds them. So the imagined
instruction from the hospital authority is not helpful.
By contrast, the following instruction would help: replace any beliefs that one holds without a
justification with beliefs that do have justifications. One can tell
whether one believes something for a reason, or with a justification. And further,
by aiming at having only justified beliefs, one should in general succeed in reaching
true beliefs since justification is, in general, conducive to truth. (Any ‘justification’
which did not increase the chances of a belief being true would not be a
justification for it after all.)
Although justification can play this second, helpful role of
providing a concrete way of aiming at true beliefs it is not so successful in
the first role mentioned above: ruling out being merely true by luck. As the
example of Sandy and the stopped clock illustrates, Sandy does have a justification for believing that it is 5pm: she can
point to the clock. Nevertheless, her belief is only true by luck because, as
the narrator of the film Withnail and I
says: even a stopped clock is right twice a day. So she has a justification for
a belief and the belief is true but no one would say that she knows the time.
Although the definition that knowledge is justified true belief
dominated philosophy for 2,000 years since Plato, the problem that one might
have a justified, true belief but still not have knowledge was first pointed
out in the 1960s by the philosopher Edmund Gettier using an example like this
one [Gettier 1963]. What follows?
It seems at first that, as a definition of knowledge, ‘justified,
true belief’ must fail (because Sandy has justified, true belief but not
knowledge). But a better response is to argue that what the example really
shows is that Sandy does not really have a proper
justification, a good enough justification for knowledge. Knowledge can still
be correctly understood as justified, true belief but not everything that one
might think of as a justification (in the example, looking at the ward clock)
really is a justification (because the clock has stopped). If so, it is a
little like the definition of stickiness from earlier: ‘a tendency of a body to
adhere to another on contact’. Just as only someone who understands the concept
of stickiness will understanding the concept of adhering, so only someone who
can understand the concept of knowledge can understand the kind of
justification it needs. Knowledge and justification are a pair of concepts that
one learns, in learning a first language, at the same time. The definition,
whilst not explaining knowledge to someone who does not already understand it,
highlights the essential connection between knowledge truth and justification. If so, nursing knowledge has to have the right kind of
justification. The route to knowledge to underpin nursing practice will be, as
suggested above, through suitable justification.
We will end this section by returning to the question we first
raised. Why should nurses aim to have knowledge
of their subject? What is the value
of knowledge? In the light of the discussion so far part of the answer is this.
Because knowledge, unlike say mere rumour or public opinion on which nursing
might otherwise be based, is by definition true, aiming at knowledge is aiming
at truth. Now it may seem obvious in a theoretical or contemplative discipline why
one should aim at truth in one’s thinking. Cosmologists, for example, want to
understand how the universe works just for the sake of understanding it. And
hence they should aim at true beliefs just for their sake. But there is a
further reason to aim at truth for nursing.
This is because nursing is a practical discipline. It aims not just to understand health and illness (as a merely theoretical or contemplative discipline) but, for example, to make a difference, to change people’s states of illness to health. And in general, actions – for example, medical interventions, or acts of caring – based on true beliefs are more likely to succeed than those based on false ones. So nurses should aim at having true beliefs in order that their practical interventions in the lives of their patients are more likely to be successful. But because there are no intrinsic signs or symptoms of true beliefs that mark them out from false beliefs, the route to this is via a suitable justification which forms part of the conceptually rich idea of knowledge.
This is because nursing is a practical discipline. It aims not just to understand health and illness (as a merely theoretical or contemplative discipline) but, for example, to make a difference, to change people’s states of illness to health. And in general, actions – for example, medical interventions, or acts of caring – based on true beliefs are more likely to succeed than those based on false ones. So nurses should aim at having true beliefs in order that their practical interventions in the lives of their patients are more likely to be successful. But because there are no intrinsic signs or symptoms of true beliefs that mark them out from false beliefs, the route to this is via a suitable justification which forms part of the conceptually rich idea of knowledge.
In this section, we have raised a fundamental question: why
should nurses aim at knowledge. By ‘unpacking’ the concept of knowledge we have
suggested answers which connect to the value of truth, the role of
justification as a way of aiming at truth and the practical ambitions of
nursing to intervene in patients’ lives. There are further, complementary
reasons we could have explored. For example, to identify someone, such as a
particular member of a multiple disciplinary team, as knowing a patient’s history is to mark out what he or she says on
the matter as reliable. Knowledge can be used to mark out whom to trust in
cooperative disciplines like nursing.
But although we have talked about the knowledge which underpins
nursing practice or ‘nursing knowledge’, there are reasons to think that the
diversity of forms of knowledge that nurses need to know makes the phrase
‘nursing knowledge’ misleading. Towards the end of the chapter we will
provocatively suggest that there is no such thing as ‘nursing knowledge’ and
that nursing is as much an art as a science. But in the next three sections, we
will discuss some broad divisions of kinds of knowledge and suggest that
nursing straddles each divide. Hence in each case, the generation of new
knowledge to underpin practice has to draw on distinct methods and approaches
which adds to the challenge of being a modern nurse.