(This is a draft paper written whilst my mind has been dominated by feelings of dullness and misery. I have at least found trying to concentrate on philosophy some consolation.)
Introduction: disorder and naturalism
The concepts of illness, disease
and disorder all share a prima facie normative character. Even Robert Kendell,
who defended a plainly factual account, conceded that appearance in his 1975
paper ‘The concept of disease and its implications for psychiatry’. He writes:
Before we can begin to decide
whether mental illnesses are legitimately so called we have first to agree on
an adequate definition of illness; to decide if you like what is the defining
characteristic or the hallmark of disease… By 1960 the ‘lesion’ concept of
disease … had been discredited beyond redemption, but nothing had yet been put
in its place. It was clear, though, that its successor would have to be based
on a statistical model of the relationship between normality and abnormality…
But… [a statistical model] fails to distinguish between deviations from the
norm which are harmful, like hypertension, those which are neutral, like great
height, and those which are positively beneficial, like superior intelligence.
[Kendell 1975: 309]
The normative aspect of disease
is suggested in this passage by the dimension spanning harm to benefit. This is
a distinction beyond mere degree of difference from a statistical norm. It is
normative as opposed to merely (statistically) normal. But normative notions
present a challenge for the philosophical programme of placing complex concepts
into a conception of nature, or ‘naturalising’ them as that project is usually
known especially given the most influential version of philosophical
naturalism: reductionism. (In his book on Philosophical Naturalism David
Papineau argues that its fundamental characteristic is ‘the thesis that all
natural phenomena are, in a sense to be made precise, physical’ [Papineau 1993:
1]. Hence showing how concepts pick out real and natural features of the world
involves, ultimately, reducing them to physical concepts.)
The reason that normativity
presents a challenge to philosophical naturalism so understood is that, on an
influential neo-Humean view, the natural world is not itself the source of
normativity: thinking subjects are. As Hamlet says, on this view: ‘there is nothing either good or bad, but thinking makes it so’. Thus normative concepts cannot be thought of
describing the natural world but reflecting human subjectivity. This is clearest
in cases where the normativity concerned, like Hamlet’s line, takes the form of
explicit value judgements.
Here is one such example in the
philosophy of disorder. KWM (Bill) Fulford defends an account of illness as an
endogenously caused failure of ordinary doing [Fulford 1989]. He argues against
both Thomas Szasz, who contrasts mental and physical illness, and Robert Kendell,
who assimilates them as value-free, that mental illness and physical illness
are both value terms [Szasz 1960]. The
idea that illness comprises an internally generated failure of ordinary doing explains its values-ladenness because
the concept of failure itself suggests an ineliminable negative value
judgement. But Fulford also argues that differences of opinion about the value
judgements need not generally imply error because they do not answer to
anything objective. Value judgements are projections of a subject’s sentiments
onto the world and hence differences of opinions should be explored rather than
corrected [eg Fulford 2004]. Hence the class of illnesses does not pick out
anything objective. It is a reflection of both worldly facts but also
subjective values about which there can be rational disagreement.
Fulford’s account does not fit reductionist
naturalism. Illness is not in that sense a ‘natural’ concept but an alloy of worldly
fact and human value with the latter underpinning the prima facie normative
element of illness. To naturalise illness – at least in accord with the
dominant reductionist reading of that term – would require some way to account
for the normative dimension in value-free and naturalistic terms. That
possibility is the subject matter of this chapter. To investigate its prospects
I will discuss Jerome Wakefield’s influential harmful dysfunction model of disorder.
Wakefield’s harmful dysfunction model
To be clear from the start: Wakefield
does not attempt to provide a
value-free analysis of illness or disease or disorder (unlike others such as
Christopher Boorse and Robert Kendell who do.) (Note that although, perhaps
influenced by Boorse, Wakefield talks of ‘disorder’ rather than ‘illness’ or ‘disease’,
he does not suggest any firm distinctions between them; he comments: ‘some
writers draw distinctions among disorder,
disease, and illness. Disorder is
perhaps the broader term because it covers traumatic injuries as well as
disease/illness. I ignore these differences’ [Wakefield 1992: 374] I will
follow his lead.) But he suggests that disorder can be analysed as a
conjunction of one specific value and a value-free medical science core.
On his account, the normative
dimension is divided between two elements. It features in the value ‘harm’
which forms one conjunct and helps encode the practical aims of medicine to
intervene in only particular cases, the harmful ones. But it is also present in
the concept of a dysfunction which turns out to be ‘anchored in evolutionary
theory’ [Wakefield 1999: 465]. The resulting ‘harmful dysfunction analysis’ contrasts
with Fulford’s analysis in that, in the latter, facts and values mingle ‘all
the way down’. By contrast Wakefield’s approach aims to characterise a purely
descriptive core for medical science
using the idea of biological functions. In other words, the normative component
of any illness is divided into an irreducibly value-laden element of harm and
into a deviation from a biological function which is then reduced to, or
naturalised via, descriptive biological theory. The class of biological
dysfunctions is thus a natural class even if the broader class of disorder is
not. The focus here is that narrow class.
The challenge of giving a
descriptive, non-normative or non-evaluative account of function to explain this
core element of disorder goes hand in hand with giving an account of failure of function. Only if an account
can be given of what a divergence of
the behaviour of a system from its function comprises has the notion of a
function which could be successfully or
unsuccessfully executed been substantiated. But if such an account of function can
be given in value-free, descriptive terms, then it would ipso facto successfully
account for failure of function. Thus it would be a mistake to assume that in
characterising disorder partly as a failure
of function, Wakefield has already conceded the game to value theorists because
‘failure’ is an evaluative concept as Fulford seems to suggest [Fulford 1999,
2000]. If function can be analysed in descriptive terms then so can ‘failure’
of function: it is any divergence from function. An apparently normative or evaluative
concept would be reduced to a value-free descriptive analysis.
It may still seem that, in the
case of function, a non-normative descriptive account is a hopeless non-starter
precisely because the distinction between success
and failure surely cannot be reduced
to a purely factual or descriptive vocabulary. But just such descriptivist
accounts of natural function have been proposed elsewhere as part of the wider
legacy of Darwin. In the philosophy of language and thought, for example, Ruth
Garrett Millikan proposes that the
intentionality or ‘aboutness’ of thoughts and beliefs can be naturalised using
the notion of biological functions [see especially Millikan 1984]. She argues
that even conscious human purposes – paradigm instances of genuine teleology – are
susceptible to this form of reductionist naturalism [Millikan 1998: 309].
Much has been written on the
definition of function. Two broad approaches are perhaps most influential: the
views of Cummins and Wright. Rachel Cooper summarises their differences thus:
Of the best known positions,
those who adopt Cummins-type views [Cummins 1975] claim that the function of a
sub-system is whatever it normally currently does that contributes towards the
goals of a larger system. On such an account the function of the heart is to
pump blood around the body, as this is what hearts currently normally do that
contributes to the organism surviving and reproducing. On the other hand, those
who favour Wright-style approaches [Wright 1973] think that the function of a
sub-system is fixed by its history. In the biological domain, the
Wright-function of a sub-system is whatever it was naturally selected to do.
[Cooper 2007: 30-1]
Elsewhere Cooper suggests other
options and suggests that there are prima facie difficulties with all of them
for the analysis of disorder or disease.
For the function of X to be Z any
of the following might be considered necessary:
1. X was originally selected
because it does Z.2. In the recent past selection has been responsible for maintaining X because it does Z.
3. Currently selection is responsible for maintaining X because it does Z.
4. At all times X has been selected because it does Z.
It is difficult to choose between these options as each is associated with potential problems. [Cooper 2002: 268]
It turns out that the process that explains the prototypical non-accidental benefits is natural selection acting to increase inclusive fitness of the organism. [
But the (putative) complexity of the intentional object of a mental state does not, of course, entail the complexity of the mental state itself. It’s here that LOT ventures beyond mere Intentional Realism... LOT claims that mental states - and not just their propositional objects - typically have constituent structure. [Fodor 1987: 136]
One of the problems that Cooper highlights is that if one opts for the original selective advantages of some trait which, as a matter of fact, now also prima facie serves another function then failure of that current prima facie function will not count as disease. But if recent history is taken to be key, then, because human societies and technologies now affect actual reproduction, traits which might seem prima facie to be dysfunctional but which are compensated for through human intervention cannot count as diseases. I will ignore these particular difficulties here.
Both Wakefield and Millikan
favour a historical approach (like Wright’s) connecting functions to actual evolutionary
selective histories and, as will become clearer, this is most apt for the reductionist
project in question. Roughly speaking the biological or proper function of a particular
trait of an organism is what explains the evolutionary success and survival
value of that trait. (In fact, Millikan defines functions within an account of
reproductively established families but the details of her theory will not
matter here.)
Crucially, for the purposes of
capturing the prima facie normativity of disorder (Walkefield) and
intentionality (Millikan), biological functions are distinct from dispositions.
The biological function of a trait and its dispositions can diverge.
Engineering limitations might cause the actual behavioural dispositions of a
trait to diverge from the biological function it thus only partially
exemplifies. Further, the divergences might themselves be life threatening and
play no positive part in explaining the value of the trait. The best
explanation of the survival of that organism and those like it cites the function
which helped propagation or predator evasion, for example, and not those
aspects of its behavioural dispositions which diverged unhelpfully from it.
This point is sometimes put by
saying that what matters is not which traits or dispositions are selected, but
what function they are selected for.
The distinction between ‘selection of’ and ‘selection for’ can be illustrated
by the example of a child’s toy [Sober 1984]. A box allows objects of different
shapes to be posted into it through differently shaped slots in the lid. The
round slot thus allows the insertion of balls, for example. It may be that the
actual balls allowed through or ‘selected’ in one case are all green. But they
are selected for their round cross
section and not their green colour. Millikan stresses the fact that the
biological function of a trait may be displayed in only a minority of actual
cases. It is the function of sperm to fertilise an egg but the great majority
of sperm fails in this regard [Millikan 1984: 34]. Since biological functions
can diverge from mere dispositions, they have extra resources necessary for
accounting for the idea of failure of
function. The distinction between success and failure of a system, organism or
organ can be defined by reference to its functioning in accord with its
biological function.
Wakefield’s work on disorder is
in the same tradition: providing a reductionist account of a problematic
concept by appeal to evolutionary theory. He offers an initially distinct, but
eventually similar, account of natural functions. Drawing on essentialist
accounts of natural kinds, such as water or gold, he suggests that natural
functions likewise have an underlying essence. Thus natural functions are
defined as sharing whatever the initially unknown essential process is which
explains prototypical non-accidental beneficial effects such as eyes seeing.
This is a surprising claim given that what unites natural kinds such as gold or
water are first order physical properties. No first order physical properties
unite natural functions. But Wakefield
goes on to invoke explanation and natural selection in a much more standard
way:
A natural function of a
biological mechanism is an effect of the mechanism that explains the existence,
maintenance or nature of the mechanism via the same essential process (whatever
it is) by which prototypical nonaccidental beneficial effects... explain the
mechanism which cause them...
Thus, like Millikan, Wakefield relies on an
account of natural function drawn from explanation within evolutionary theory
to distinguish those dispositions which accord with a system’s naturally
selected function from those which do not.
However, despite this connection
between the prima facie normativity of the concept of disorder and the
normativity, albeit rooted in evolutionary history, of biological functions,
there remains an ambiguity between two possible reductionist aims for such an account.
In the next section I will clarify this through a detour into the philosophy of
thought or mental content. I will then argue, in the following section, that an
objection derived from Wittgenstein’s discussion of rules threatens one version
but not the other. In the final section I will consider which aim is
appropriate to naturalising mental disorder.
What kind of reductionist naturalism?
In this section I will distinguish between two aims for
reductionist naturalism which can be compared to two horns of the Euthyphro
dilemma. But to make this more concrete, I will characterise the difference
using the actual aims of two competing, but reductionist, approaches in the
philosophy of content: those of Millikan, already mentioned, and of Jerry
Fodor.
In the lengthy appendix to his book Psychosemantics, Jerry Fodor articulates a general argument for
reductionism in the philosophy of content.
I suppose that sooner or later the physicists will complete the
catalogue they’ve been compiling of the ultimate and irreducible properties of things.
When they do, the likes of spin, charm and charge will perhaps
appear upon their list. But aboutness surely won’t; intentionality simply
doesn’t go that deep. It’s hard to see... how one can be a Realist about intentionality
without also being, to some extent or other, a Reductionist. If the semantic and
intentional are real properties of things, it must be in virtue of their identity
with (or supervenience on?) properties that are neither intentional nor
semantic. If aboutness is real, it must be really something else. [Fodor 1987: 97]
The promise of the programme is that intentionality itself will be
fitted into a conception of nature – or ‘naturalised’ – by a reduction to
properties which are not essentially or intrinsically intentional or semantic. Since
the latter are supposed to constitute the former (through identity or
supervenience) it is not that they are not intentional or semantic, but they
are not essentially so. Thus the concepts in the reduction base can be understood
independently of grasp of the concepts to be understood thus serving a project
of philosophical naturalism.
The work of the rest of the book looks at first sight to be a
contribution to this task through the articulation of what Fodor calls a ‘representational
theory of mind’. This comprises a ‘language of thought’ (LOT) to explain the
relationships between mental representations construed as internal vehicles of mental
content combined with a version of a causal theory of reference (an asymmetric dependence
theory) connecting those internal vehicles to the world.
But, on reflection, whilst, if successful, the representational
theory of mind would be a step towards a reduction of intentionality, it is not
that the actual aim of the representational theory of mind as set out in Psychosemantics is quite as radical as
the argument in the appendix. Consider the argument that mental representations
must have a structure to map the structure of mental contents.
Practically everybody thinks that the objects of
intentional states are in some way complex: for example, that what you believe
when you believe that... P & Q is... something composite, whose elements
are - as it might be - the proposition that P and the proposition that Q.
The aim of the account seems to be to explain how it is possible
for thinkers to think thoughts with the right systematic relations to other
thoughts. It is possible if there are
inner vehicles of thoughts with an isomorphous structure to the structure of
thought and, in turn, if the syntactic properties of those vehicles mirror
their semantic relations and are suitably connected to their causal properties.
Fodor attempts to show that it is not mysterious – that it is natural – that creatures
like us can think the thoughts we can. If I may use the phrase the ‘space of
reasons’ to stand for the rational relations between thought contents and
between them and the world, it seems that Fodor takes his question to be:
·
Given the space of reasons, how is it possible for
creatures like us to respond to it?
His answer is a piece of a priori engineering design. We must be
creatures with an innate conceptual repertoire carried by a language of
thought. This is still a form of reductionist naturalism. The fact that,
medical limitations aside, humans can grasp a potential infinity of thoughts
and chart the rational relations between them can seem puzzling and call for
philosophical attention. The representational theory of mind is an attempt to
make that less mysterious by showing how it would be possible for suitably
engineered creatures to have those characteristics. But it is less radical than
it might be because, within the main body of the text at least, it takes the
conceptual connections themselves for granted.
Millikan, by contrast, aims to do something more ambitious with her
evolutionary, or teleosemantic, theory of mental content. As summarised above,
she deploys a tool which seems more promising than a causal theory of reference
to account for mental content because it is itself an apparently normative
notion: biological or proper function. A biological function is normative
because it sets a standard against which the actual behaviour or dispositions
of a biological trait or subsystem can be compared. She deploys this idea not
just aim to explain how possessing mental content is the proper function of
some cognitive system. Rather, particular representational contents are
supposed to be explained in this way. The contents carried by inner vehicles
are specified via the proper functions of those vehicles: that for which they
are selected. Hence the selective advantages conferred must be characterisable in
non-intentional terms. The meaning or content carried must drop out of the evolutionary
theory rather than presupposed in specifying the advantage.
The aim of this analysis is thus more ambitious than Fodor’s
project because Millikan aims to naturalise the structure of conceptual
connections or ‘the space of reasons’ itself. Assuming that logic charts the
rational connections between contents it is significant that Millikan claims
that given a teleosemantic account, logic itself will become ‘the first of the natural
sciences’ [Millikan 1984: 11]. So her key question is something like:
·
Given our biological natures, how is it possible
for creatures like us to respond to what we take to be the space of reasons, whatever
it is.
The difference in actual ambition between Fodor and Millikan is
akin to the Euthyphro dilemma. Given a suitable theology, the following
biconditional would be true:
·
For any act x: x is pious if and only if x is loved
by the gods.
The dilemma stems from considering the ‘order of determination’,
in Crispin Wright’s phrase, of this biconditional [Wright 1992]. Is the pious loved
by the gods because it is pious, or is it pious because it is loved by the gods?
Fodor’s and Millikan’s projects take opposing views. In effect, Fodor adopts
the first horn and derives a priori engineering constraints on the gods (or
thinkers) given that we know that they are able to track piety (or the space of
reasons), antecedently understood. Millikan, by contrast, adopts the second
horn and aims to explain piety (or the space of reasons) by describing the engineering
of the gods (or thinkers) in independent (of piety or the space of reasons)
evolutionary terms.
This distinction matters to the force of an objection that can be
raised against Millikan’s programme which I will now summarise.
A Wittgensteinian objection
to Millikan’s project
There is a familiar objection to Millikan’s programme based on
Wittgenstein’s rule following considerations. It is tempting to think that
meaning or mental content needs some sort of vehicle such as sign or symbol. Any
such sign can, however, be interpreted in an unlimited number of ways and thus
needs to be coupled with the correct interpretation. This point is often
emphasised by commentators by suggesting interpretations of even extended
demonstrations by example of the meaning of words or of mathematical series
which are consistent with the examples given deviate or are ‘bent’ in some
future application [eg Blackburn 1984]. But if mental content is explained as a
mental sign which stands in need of the correct interpretation then the content
of the interpretation will also need to be similarly underpinned. And this
initiates a vicious infinite regress.
“But how can a rule shew me what I have to do at this
point? Whatever I do is, on some interpretation, in accord with the rule.” – That
is not what we ought to say, but rather: any interpretation still hangs in the
air along with what it interprets, and cannot give it any support.
Interpretations by themselves do not determine meaning. [Wittgenstein 1953
§198]
The same goes for accounting for understanding written or spoken
signs or symbols. In the absence of any coherent account of a final
interpretation which somehow blocks the regress, any account of mental content
which depends on an interpretation faces a challenge.
Millikan’s teleosemantic account of mental content is a form of interpretation-based
theory. Past behaviour is a set of signs to be interpreted. Like the interpretation
of signs, such behaviour is consistent with an unlimited number of possible functions
or rules including both continuations that seem natural and logical and an unlimited
number of other ‘bent’ rules that deviate in unnatural ways. The normativity of
a function implies that not every aspect of the behaviour of a trait or
subsystem need match the function: what the trait is for. A trait may fail to
match the function for which it was selected. What ensures the determinacy of biological
function – what selects just one of the possible rules – is a particular explanation of the persistence of trait
over evolutionary time. If the potential rewards of a trait are sufficiently
great it may be that actual behavioural dispositions of previous instances of
the trait only rarely match the function which explains the trait’s
persistence. Hence the potential gap between actual past performance and the
appropriate functional explanation. But the lesson from the discussion of ‘bent’
rules is that finite past behaviour could be explained as exemplifying many different
or ‘bent’ functions, all of which would have been equally successful in the past
but which would diverge in the future.
(Note also that this worry is not merely a kind of Quinean
marginal indeterminacy akin to the difference between rabbits and undetached
rabbit parts. Competing bent rules might be utterly different in future
applications. By what principle is just one selected? I will return to this thought
at the end.)
Millikan’s considers and responds to this objection in ‘Truth
Rules, Hoverflies, and the Kripke-Wittgenstein Paradox’. Male hoverflies spend their
time hovering and waiting for female hover flies to pass by at which point they
accelerate in pursuit. ‘[T]he geometry of motion dictates that to intercept the
female the male must make a turn that is 1800 away from the target minus about
1/10 of the vector angular velocity (measured in degrees per second) of the
target’s image across his retina’ [Millikan 1993: 219]. Millikan calls this the
‘proximal hoverfly rule’ and suggests that male hoverflies are genetically
programmed to follow it. That is, they have some internal mechanism ‘of a kind
that historically proliferated in part because it was responsible for producing
conformity to the proximal hoverfly rule, hence for getting male and female
hoverflies together.’ [ibid: 219] So the biological function of the mechanism
is to follow that rule.
But the behaviour of actual hoverflies may not accord with just
that. One possibility is that hoverflies have some optical blindspots such that
a female arriving in the blindspot of a male provokes no reaction. Such a
possibility, however, would not be part of what explains the continued
existence of the mechanism in the fly population. It would be noise rather than
signal. The more worrying possibility is a rule which accords with all past
successful fly on fly action but which diverges in the future. What in the
evolutionary historical record could rule that out? Millikan dismisses such
possibilities as follows:
[The ‘bent’ rule] is not a rule the hoverfly has a biological
purpose to follow. For it is not because their behaviour coincided with that rule
that the hoverfly’s ancestors managed to catch females, and hence to proliferate.
In saying that, I don’t have any particular theory of the nature of explanation
up my sleeve. But surely, on any reasonable account, a complexity that can simply
be dropped from the explanans without affecting the tightness of the relation of
explanans to explanandum is not a functioning part of the explanation. [Millikan
1993: 221]
This is rather a brisk response. A key element of it is that the
bent rule contains a complexity which Millikan’s preferred explanation lacks.
Her explanation is simpler. But from what perspective is her explanation
simpler?
In the case of trying to naturalise mental content, her explanans
is the meaning or content of particular vehicles of content. But she cannot
invoke our prior grasp of what such contents seem more natural – of what it
would be natural to mean – since that
is what is supposed to drop out of, rather than being presupposed by, her
analysis. And, of course, the content of the proper function is not just a matter
of looking to behavioural dispositions but selecting a function which best explains
them. But without presupposing the pattern that meaning imposes, the pattern of
the space of reasons, what other principle is there to say what makes for a
simpler explanation?
Millikan’s response would be legitimate for an attempt to answer
the question I have suggested that Fodor attempts (despite his Appendix) to
answer:
·
Given the space of reasons, how is it possible for
creatures like us to respond to it?
Fodor’s implicit question presupposes, rather than seeking to
explain, the pattern of normative liaisons between mental contents. Answering
that question, it is not illicit to
deploy a notion of simplicity that presupposes a prior grasp of the space of
reasons because that is not what the question seeks to answer. But Millikan’s
question is more ambitious and hence it is illicit in attempting it to presuppose
a notion of simplicity that is based on prior grasp of the space of reasons.
Biological function and
illness, disease and disorder
What then is the reductionist aim of appealing to biological functions
in the philosophy of mental disorder? Two options can be articulated by translating
from Fodor’s and Millikan’s questions in the philosophy of content. I suggested
that Fodor’s question was:
·
Given the space of reasons, how is it possible for
creatures like us to respond to them?
Translated into the context of naturalising disorder gives something
like:
·
Given the concept of disorder, how is it possible
for creatures like us to suffer it?
Unlike the parallel question in the philosophy of content, however,
this question does not seem worth an a priori answer. I do not mean to
presuppose an articulated theory of what is, and isn’t, worth philosophical
attention. But there seems no pressing need to articulate a general theory of a
failure to meet a normative standard by contrast with the felt need in the
parallel semantic case to articulate a general theory of how it might be
possible to meet one. Thus this question is not an appropriate way to model
reductionism about the concept of mental disorder. What of the other option?
Millikan’s question was:
·
Given our biological natures, how is it possible
for creatures like us to respond to what we take to be the space of reasons, whatever
it is?
Translated into the philosophy of mental disorder gives question
something like:
·
Given our biological natures, how is it possible
for creatures like us to suffer what we take to be disorder, whatever it is.
Millikan’s looks the better model question for the philosophy of medicine.
It makes questioning the nature of the concept of illness itself central rather
than something presupposed.
It may be objected, however, that this cannot apply to Wakefield’s
analysis of disorder as harmful dysfunction because he relies on an approach
which he describes using the phrase ‘black box’. The notion of a natural
function is defined as sharing whatever the initially unknown essential process
is which explains prototypical non-accidental beneficial effects such as eyes
seeing. It merely transpires – it comes as an a posteriori discovery – that the
process that explains the prototypical non-accidental benefits is natural
selection acting to increase inclusive fitness of the organism. And hence, the
objection might run, this cannot be used to shed light on what is meant by the
kind of dysfunction that underpins – when conjoined with harm – the idea of a
disorder.
That objection goes too quickly, however. Although it is true
that Wakefield does not engage in traditional conceptual analysis to underpin
his conception of function, and hence dysfunction, that fact does not rule out
the use of the supposedly empirically derived conception to shed light on the
nature of function itself. It does not imply that he has to restrict himself
merely to the kind of a priori engineering that Fodor attempts.
Furthermore, there is positive reason to think that he does more.
One of the virtues that Wakefield claims for his analysis is that it is able to
hold contemporary psychiatric taxonomy to account. In his persuasive
co-authored book (with Allan Horwitz) The
Loss of Sadness, for example, he argues that depression is over diagnosed
because ‘normal sadness’ – that is sadness that is in accord with human
emotional biological function – is mistaken for genuine, pathological
depression [Horwitz & Wakefield 2007]. But since, he argues, mental
disorder presupposes an underlying biological dysfunction, however unpleasant
grief is, for example, it cannot be a disorder or an illness providing it is
serving its (presumed) biological function. Given that the analysis is used to
explain the very idea of disorder (via the underlying notion of dysfunction)
the form of reductionist naturalism belongs to the more radical second horn.
But if so, because it shares the task of naturalising the normativity
of pathology, Wittgenstein’s objection is a serious objection. That is, a biological
teleological account cannot rule out wildly divergent accounts of the functions
in play, functions which explain the presence of traits. And if so, we need a better
version of naturalism for the philosophy of disorder.
A Quinean response?
My attempt to shed light on the nature of, and hence prospects
for, reductionism in the philosophy of disorder has turned on an analogy
between it and the philosophy of content and the prospects for reductionism
about semantics. But it might be objected that there is a key disanalogy
between the two cases.
Consider an argument often compared with Wittgenstein’s
discussion of rules and meaning: Quine’s argument for the indeterminacy of
translation [Quine 1990]. (Since the relation between indeterminacy of
translation, inscrutability
of reference and holophrastic indeterminacy are subject to interpretation and debate
within Quine scholarship, a rough summary of one aspect of the argument will
suffice.) Quine approaches the study of meaning via a
particular methodological constraint.
In psychology one may or may not be a behaviourist, but in
linguistics one has no choice. Each of us learns his language by observing
other people’s verbal behaviour and having his own faltering verbal behaviour
observed and reinforced and corrected by others… There is nothing in linguistic
meaning, then, beyond what is to be gleaned from overt behaviour in overt
circumstances [Quine 1990: 5]
This reflects a commitment to the idea that facts about meaning
are public and shareable. But Quine goes further in limiting the kind of facts available
to fix the facts about meaning to those which fit a particular scientistic
world view. The project is constrained by connecting prompted ascent to
sentences with environmental stimuli physicalistically described. These facts,
however, underdetermine the translation of sentences. Since they are the only
relevant facts, this implies that sentence translation is indeterminate.
With this argument in place, one might object that the comparison
deployed so far between meaning and the concept of disorder is inappropriate. Whilst
Quinean indeterminacy is revisionary of our pre-philosophical concept of
meaning, the concept of disorder can more readily tolerate some such slack. So
on the assumption that the Wittgensteinian argument outlined in previous sections
sufficiently matches the Quinean argument just sketched, and on the assumption
that some degree of indeterminacy is no threat to the medical concept of
disorder, the claim that the project of reducing the concept of disorder to
naturalistic terms introduces an element of indeterminacy is no threat to the
project.
Such a response fails, however, because the supposed parallel between
Wittgenstein and Quine is misleading. Quine accepts a degree of indeterminacy in
his positive account of meaning. He thinks that the evidence that fixes meaning
only goes so far. This is, of course, because Quine builds in an assumption that
the evidence has to be physicalistically described. Against that background, meaning
would be indeterministic. But what, aside from scientism, justifies that restriction?
Wittgenstein, by contrast, does not think that meaning is indeterministic.
The contexts which play a role in constraining it are described in intentional terms.
The apparent parallel just sketched between Quine and Wittgenstein is not part of
the latter’s positive account but rather a reductio ad absurdum of reductionism.
More significant, however, is that Wittgenstein’s negative argument does not deliver
merely a domesticated indeterminacy but rather no shaping of content in the future
at all and hence undermines the very possibility of radical reductionist
naturalism in the case of disorder too.
Conclusion
I suggested that if the Wittgensteinian argument against the more
radical reductionist aim is successful whilst there is no rational reason to
pursue the more modest aim then the philosophy of disorder needs a better
conception of philosophical naturalism. Fortunately, there are other approaches
which can still justifiably claim to be forms of philosophical naturalism.
One can, for example, sketch the broader context in which
apparently puzzling concepts are used in such a way as to make their use clear.
One example of this is the way that Daniel Dennett attempts to demystify the
mental by describing the ‘intentional stance’ within which mental properties
are characterised [Dennett 1991]. Dennett’s aim is, by describing how the
stance works and by suggesting that it is merely one of many possible stances
for making sense of the world, to show how the properties so ascribed are
perfectly natural even though they cannot be reduced to the properties deployed
in other stances, such as the physical stance.
Dennett’s approach is one version of naturalism without
reductionism. It helps to highlight the key assumption behind Fodor’s argument
for reductionism quoted earlier in this chapter. The passage starts with an
appeal to the shape of a future, completed physics. That serves as the
benchmark of the really real and hence prompts the challenge for puzzling
concepts. If they do not appear on the ultimate list then either they mark an
unreal property or they must be reducible to concepts on the list. The
challenge, however, presupposes without justifying the assumption that the
physicists’ list is such a benchmark and that assumption can be contested.
John McDowell, for example, has suggested that nature is not
restricted to what can be described using the vocabulary of the physical
sciences. Criticising a reductionist construal of naturalism, McDowell, for
example, says:
What is at work here is a
conception of nature that can seem sheer common sense, though it was not always
so; the conception I mean was made available only by a hard-won achievement of
human thought at a specific time, the time of the rise of modern science.
Modern science understands its subject matter in a way that threatens, at
least, to leave it disenchanted...The image marks a contrast between two kinds
of intelligibility: the kind that is sought by (as we call it) natural science,
and the kind we find in something when we place it in relation to other
occupations of ‘the logical space of reasons’, to repeat a suggestive phrase
from Wilfrid Sellars. If we identify nature with what natural science aims to
make comprehensible, we threaten, at least, to empty it of meaning. By way of
compensation, so to speak, we see it as the home of a perhaps inexhaustible
supply of intelligibility of the other kind, the kind we find in a phenomenon
when we see it as governed by natural law. It was an achievement of modern
thought when this second kind of intelligibility was clearly marked off from
the first. [McDowell 1994: 701].
McDowell commends a different response to the prospects of a
failure of reductionism. Rather than regarding this as impugning the reality of
the properties or concepts concerned it may merely show that reductionists have
started with an impoverished conception of the real or of nature. Central to
McDowell’s picture is the possibility of undermining a dualism of normativity
and nature. Nature itself may contain norms, it may be ‘fraught with ought’ in
Sellars’s phrase. It is not restricted to what fits within the ‘realm of law’
articulated by the physical sciences, but also includes those emergent patterns
and properties that have to be fitted within a different pattern of
intelligibility: the ‘space of reasons’. This phrase marks in McDowell’s work
(following Sellars) the rational pattern of intentional states (broadly
construed to include ethical demands; it is thus comparable with but broader
than Dennett’s intentional patterns [Dennett 1991]). But an analogous
conclusion could be drawn for other, nonintentional, concepts for which
naturalists have also attempted philosophical reduction (eg necessity,
causality etc). Again the failure of an attempt at reduction in these cases
need not undermine their reality.
McDowell’s views are influenced by a reading of Aristotle’s
ethical views. He argues, elsewhere, that that both moral values and also
secondary qualities form part of the fabric of the world [McDowell 1983]. The suggestion
is that there may be features of the world for which one needs a particular
kind of mind, perhaps formed partly as the result of training to detect,
respond to and even to conceptualise. Thus one needs an appropriate moral
education to understand, be sensitive, and resonate, to the demands that, say
kindness, makes on one in particular circumstances [McDowell 1979]. But just
because these are demands that can be understood only from such a perspective
does not undermine their basic reality.
Applied to the concept of disorder, such a conception of
philosophical naturalism suggests a different approach to the prima facie
normativity of mental illness and disease from reducing it. By contrast with
apportioning it either to the irreducibly normative value of harm or anchored,
descriptively, in evolutionary theory, a more relaxed conception of nature
allows that the normativity may be both more complex but no less part of the
natural world. This has an important consequence. A substantial theory of disorder
such as Wakefield’s forges a connection between it and dysfunction. On a
reductionist interpretation, the latter concept has to be understood
independently of, and hence shed independent light on, the former. That
connection, however, may be informative even without the reductionism. Our
grasp of disorder may contribute to our grasp of function and dysfunction and
vice versa. And hence Wakefield’s analysis of the difference between, for
example, sadness and depression may remain suggestive and helpful even in a new
philosophical setting.
Acknowledgement
This chapter was written whilst a fellow of the Institute for Advanced Study, University of Durham. My thanks both to the IAS, Durham and the University of Central Lancashire for granting me research leave.
Bibliography
Blackburn, S. (1984) ‘The individual strikes back’ Synthese 58: 281-301
Boorse, C. (1975) ‘On the distinction between disease and illness’
Philosophy and Public Affairs 5:
49-68
Cooper, R. (2002) ‘Disease’ Studies
in History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Sciences, 33:
263-282
Cooper, R. (2007) Psychiatry
and Philosophy of Science Durham: Acumen
Cummins,
R. (1975) ‘Functional Analysis’ Journal of Philosophy 72:
741–65
Dennett, D. (1991) ‘Real patterns’ Journal of Philosophy 88: 27-51
Fodor, J.A. (1987) Psychosemantics.
Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press
Fulford, K.W.M. (1989)
Moral Theory and Medical Practice, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
Fulford, K.W.M. (1999)
‘Nine variations and a coda on the theme of an evolutionary definiction of
dysfunction’ Journal of Abnormal Psychology 108: 412-420
Fulford, K.W.M. (2000)
‘Teleology without tears’ Philosophy, Psychiatry and Psychology 7 77-94
Fulford, K.W.M. (2004)
‘Ten Principles of Values-Based Medicine’ in Radden, J. (ed) The Philosophy
of Psychiatry: A Companion, New York: Oxford University Press: 205-34
Horwitz, A.V. and Wakefield, J.C. (2007) The Loss of Sadness,
Oxford: Oxford University Press
Kendell, R.E. (1975) ‘The concept of disease and its implications
for psychiatry’ British Journal of
Psychiatry 127: 305-315
McDowell, J. (1979) ‘Virtue and reason’ Monist 62: 331-350.
McDowell, J. (1983) ‘Aesthetic value, objectivity, and the fabric
of the world’ In Pleasure Preference and
Value, ed. Schaper, E. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
McDowell, J. 1994. Mind and
world. Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press.
Millikan, R.G. (1984) Language,
thought and other biological categories. Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press
Millikan, R.G. (1993) White queen
psychology, Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press
Millikan, R.G. (1995) ‘A bet with
Peacocke’ in Macdonald, C. and Macdonald, G. (eds) (1995) Philosophy of
Psychology, Oxford: Blackwell 285-292
Millikan, R.G. (1998) In defence of proper functions. In Nature’s purposes: analyses of function and
design in biology, ed. C. Allen and G. Lauder. Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press
Papineau, D. (1993) Philosophical
naturalism, Oxford: Blackwell
Quine,
W. V. O. (1960) Word and Object. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press
Sober, E. 1984. The nature
of selection. Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press
Szasz, T. (1960) ‘The myth of mental illness’ American Psychologist, 15: 113-118.
Wakefield, J.C. (1992) ‘The Concept of
Mental Disorder: On the Boundary Between Biological Facts and Social Values’ American
Psychologist 47: 373-88
Wakefield, J.C. (1999) ‘Mental disorder as a black box
essentialist concept’ Journal of Abnormal
Psychology 108, no 3: 465-472
Wittgenstein, L. (1953). Philosophical
investigations. Oxford: Blackwell
Wright, C. (1992) Truth and
objectivity. Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press
Wright,
L. (1973) ‘Functions’ Philosophical Review 82:
139–68