I’ve been reading McDowell’s recent
paper ‘Perceptual Experience: Both Relational and
Contentful’ [McDowell 2013]. Although I think I understand the broad
outlines of the picture presented – which is not to say that there are no deeply
puzzling aspects – I have been confused by the choreography in the middle.
McDowell talks about an argument with a first and second premise. But he also
talks about an argument which can be read in either a modus ponens or a modus
tollens way. I’ve been puzzled by what he’s talking about. But I now think I
have an interpretation. Crucially, there are two distinct arguments.
The argument that can be given either
a modus ponens or modus tollens spin has the following elements. There is a
premise which comprises a simple claim and a more complex conditional premise.
There’s then a simple conclusion.
Presented as modus ponens, the simple premise
is that:
- P1: the epistemic significance of experiences consists in their having content in the way they do.
- P2: If the epistemic significance of an experience consists in its having content in the way it does, then it cannot be by bringing environmental realities into view that experiences enable their subjects to know things about the environment.
- P2: If the epistemic significance of an experience consists in its having content in the way it does, then it cannot be that experiences enable their subjects to know things about the environment by bringing environmental realities into view.
- C: It cannot be by bringing environmental realities into view that experiences enable their subjects to know things about the environment.
- C: It cannot be that experiences enable their subjects to know things about the environment by bringing environmental realities into view.
Read the other way round as a modus tollens
argument, and holding the conditional constant, the conclusion is that it is not true that the epistemic significance of experiences consists in their having content in
the way they do. One such view is Travis’ in which experiences play no content-bearing
role. They are simply routes to the world for subsequent judgement. They enable
the world to be in view for subsequent conceptual judgement. Here’s the
description of that view:
We would be immune to the puzzlement those questions express
if we accepted a relational conception of the sort that refuses to conceive the
epistemic significance of experience in terms of content. On this view,
experiences contribute to one’s having knowledge about one’s environment, but
only by placing one’s surroundings in view. If one knows something about one’s
environment through perception, that is because one has made something of
things an experience places in view for one. One has brought them under
concepts, exercising cognitive capacities that are extra to having the things
in view. If someone has a knowledge-constituting warrant for a belief about how
things are in her environment, the warrant depends on the epistemic credentials
of the capacities she has exercised in applying concepts to things her
experience anyway places in view for her. So the puzzlement does not arise.
There is no application for the conception that causes it; there is no such
thing as an experience that itself provides its subject with a conclusive
warrant, or indeed any warrant, for believing something about her environment. [ibid: 149]
I don’t think that there’s a very
strong argument against this position in this paper. We know that McDowell
continues to think that it falls prey to the Myth of the Given and we know that
Travis continues to think that it doesn’t. If I am at all on track with Travis his
key idea is that it is an entirely acceptable view of the exercise of reason
that it mediates between the conceptual (which exemplifies generality,
understandings, occasionalism etc) and the non-conceptual (that which instances
general concepts) so we do not need accept McDowell’s acceptance that there is
almost a truth in the Davidsonian idea that the only thing that can serve as a
reason for a belief is another belief. (Almost
a truth because belief-like experiences can play just this role too. That’s the
point of Mind and World’s transcendental empiricism.) But I will park this
disagreement here. McDowell aims to show, at least, that it should receive no
further support from the forced choice discussed here. He can head off a reason for thinking
it obligatory. (That said, this does not seem to be the motive Travis himself has for his position which - mainly? - concerns, instead, the distinction between the conceptual, which admits of understandings, and the non-conceptual and the argument that making experience itself part of the conceptual is incoherent. For some attempts to get clear on that see this.)
Now one possible way to reject the conclusion
that provides such a further motivation for Travis’ account would be to
adopt the content view and attempt to head off the worry caused by the fact
that contents can be misleading. Sadly it won’t do for reasons which have to do
with the distinction drawn in ‘Knowledge and the internal’ between mathematics
or logic and empirical knowledge.
We might be tempted by a thought on these lines: if one takes
an experience to make knowledge available when it does not, that reflects some
flaw in one’s cognitive conduct—haste, inattention, or whatever. That way, we
could suppose an experience can conclusively warrant a belief about the
environment, consistently with the requirement that one’s self-consciousness in
enjoying it must put one in a position to know it has that epistemic
significance. It is just that to avail oneself of that possibility of knowing
the epistemic significance of an experience, one needs to ensure that one’s
cognitive conduct, in exercising one’s capacity to know the epistemic
significance of one’s experiences, is flawless. The idea would be that if one
exercised that capacity without such flaws in cognitive conduct as haste or
inattention, one would not be at risk of taking an experience to enable one to
know something about the environment when it does not.
But the trouble with this idea is that it is not credible. Taking an experience to make knowledge available when it does not can be blameless. [ibid: 150]
But the trouble with this idea is that it is not credible. Taking an experience to make knowledge available when it does not can be blameless. [ibid: 150]
So going back, both the MP/MT arguments
depend on a conditional for which there is a distinct argument ie one which isn't
the same as these MP and MT arguments. It happens earlier in the paper on p146 where
the second premise is that experiences can
appear to make knowledge about the environment available when they do not. The
more complicated first premise is in this passage:
The epistemic significance of an experience must be available
to the subject in enjoying the experience. It must reside in some aspect of the
experience’s subjective character. So on the content conception, an experience’s
having content as it does must be constitutive of its subjective character, in so
far as its subjective character is relevant to its putting its subject in touch
with her surroundings, or at least seeming to. [ibid: 146]
Now I think that McDowell accepts both
of these. But they can seem, wrongly, to lead to the conditional which drives the
MP/MT forced choice. So having set out that forced choice he has to explain why
these two premises don't lead to the conclusion of this other argument: the conditional
which drives the forced choice in the MP/MT argument.
Here the key thought is that a
possibility has gone missing in the conventional view:
The premise that has been giving us trouble is that one can
take an experience to make knowledge available when it does not. That does not
show that when an experience makes knowledge available, it is not by bringing a
suitable environmental reality into view for one. The point is just that the
capacity to be in such positions is fallible.
We take in stride the fact that a capacity to know through perception such things as that there is something red and rectangular in front of one is fallible. We must, if we are going to suppose we ever have such knowledge. What makes it look as if the capacity cannot work in the way I have described— yielding knowledge whose title to count as such depends on experience making environmental realities present to us and thereby giving us conclusive warrant for beliefs about the environment—is the thought that knowing the epistemic significance of an experience that warrants a bit of knowledge we have through that fallible capacity would have to be an act of another capacity: a separate capacity to know such things, which would have to be in principle infallible. And the argument’s second premise is that there is no such infallible capacity. But the argument fails, because the capacity by which one knows the epistemic significance of one’s experiences is not another capacity, but just the capacity whose fallibility we anyway have to take in stride. [ibid: 151]
We take in stride the fact that a capacity to know through perception such things as that there is something red and rectangular in front of one is fallible. We must, if we are going to suppose we ever have such knowledge. What makes it look as if the capacity cannot work in the way I have described— yielding knowledge whose title to count as such depends on experience making environmental realities present to us and thereby giving us conclusive warrant for beliefs about the environment—is the thought that knowing the epistemic significance of an experience that warrants a bit of knowledge we have through that fallible capacity would have to be an act of another capacity: a separate capacity to know such things, which would have to be in principle infallible. And the argument’s second premise is that there is no such infallible capacity. But the argument fails, because the capacity by which one knows the epistemic significance of one’s experiences is not another capacity, but just the capacity whose fallibility we anyway have to take in stride. [ibid: 151]
Still, this paper makes something clear which hadn't been to me, at least, before. The content of experience can be the same in veridical and misleading cases, between the good and bad disjuncts. The word ‘content’ is used in this way. Content is a highest common factor. But there’s more to experience than its content, there is the way an experience has the content it does. This marks the key difference between being a case of seeing, or a case of having the world in view, and merely enjoying/suffering an appearance.
One further interesting claim is that visual experiences share a de se character. Seeings are de re but the broader class of visual experiences are de se:
Visual experiences as such, whether seeings or not, have content that enables those that are seeings to place their subjects in such relations to objects. But that is provided for, not by a de re character that belongs to the contents of seeings, but by a de se character that belongs to the contents of visual experiences as such. When I formulate an aspect of the content of an experience with the words “(There is) something red and rectangular in front of me”, “in front of me” is schematic for a much more specific placement, in relation to me, of an apparent red rectangular thing. That is enough to secure that if the experience is a seeing, it enables me to refer, with a visually grounded demonstrative, to the red rectangular thing I see. [ibid: 155-6]
What puzzles me here is why the de re character of a reference I chose to make of my experience - the sort of thing Travis starts his story with - belongs* to the content of the seeing and not the judgement made on its basis.
(*It is hard to know how to put this. It isn't that the content is de re articulated since the content of the good and the bad disjuncts are the same: de se. But the way the content of a genuine seeing comes about is de re.)
McDowell, J. (2013) ‘Perceptual Experience: Both Relational and Contentful’ European Journal of Philosophy 21: 144-57