“The Oxford Handbook of Philosophy and Psychiatry offers the most comprehensive reference resource for this area ever published and we are delighted to announce the launch as part of the Summer School. Sponsored by Oxford University Press, the launch will open with a short address from Dr Anita Avramides (Reader in Philosophy of Mind, University of Oxford).
The book is written and edited by an international team comprising world-leading philosophers and psychiatrists, resulting in an authoritative volume. We are very happy to welcome several of these team members to the Summer School where they will be delivering key sessions:
• Values in Mental Health Practice - Professor Bill Fulford (Emeritus Professor of Philosophy and Mental Health, University of Warwick, and Member of the Philosophy Faculty, University of Oxford)
• Ordering Disorder: Mental Disorder, Brain Disorder and Therapeutic Intervention - Professor George Graham (Professor of Philosophy and Neuroscience, Georgia State University)
• Karl Jaspers and the Ethics of Incomprehensibility - Professor Giovanni Stanghellini (Professor of Dynamic Psychology and Psychopathology, University of Chieti)
These sessions form part of an intensive programme delivered through keynote lectures and seminars offering opportunities for substantial dialogue between philosophers, scientists and mental health practitioners.
The Summer School will take place at St Catherine’s College, Oxford (14 – 19 July 2013) and includes opportunities to network and socialise with fellow delegates, faculty members and invited speakers. Residential and non-residential options are available.”
Further details available: www.conted.ox.ac.uk/ox_ppss
Sunday, 24 March 2013
Saturday, 9 March 2013
Hopper, K. (2007) ‘Rethinking social recovery in schizophrenia'
The UCLan mental health reading group
has started a series of recovery related papers in advance of a planned visit
by Larry Davidson. We kicked off with Kim Hopper’s 2007 paper ‘Rethinking
social recovery in schizophrenia: What a capabilities approach might offer’.
The paper starts with the pre-history
of the recovery movement in mental healthcare, when the conception of recovery
was, as one might have expected, simply getting better, sloughing off illness
but when the best that seemed likely was, in Kraepelin’s phrase, ‘cure with defect’ (or
‘healing with scarring’). For example research in 1928 suggested a 20% recovery
rate, meaning that that proportion were able to return to expected social roles.
More recently, however, what Hopper calls ‘social recovery’ has been found to
be more common than previously expected ‘outside the hospital, when measured by
independent living and gainful employment’ [ibid: 869]. But he stresses the
importance that targeted help can make to such social recovery. This in turn
led to the development of a widespread literature about recovery with four key
themes.
1.
Renewing a sense of possibility
2.
Regaining competencies
3.
Reconnecting and finding a place in society
4.
Reconciliation work
But,
Hopper argues, this list of themes significantly neglects social context: the
difference that race, gender, poverty etc can make to mental health. The neglect
of systematic treatment of such features undermines the right to call recovery
a ‘model’.
To speak of a ‘model’ of recovery is thus misleading.
Movements are not peer-reviewed. Mobilizing committed forces means hoisting
rallying cries at odds with one another, tamping down potentially divisive
demands, and capitalizing on working misunderstandings. In making the case against
therapeutic nihilism, rethinking services, and embracing patients as active
agents in their own recuperation, this inclusive approach served well, making
common cause of potentially discordant constituencies. But the same medley of affirmation,
reckless hope and wide appeal made for later difficulties when converting
emancipating creed into actionable policy. [ibid: 871]
Hopper goes on to argue that the open
ended and moral crusading aspects of recovery have prevented it from being put
into practice. He gives the example of Jacobson’s anthropological study of Wisconsin
in which institutional inertia has prevented significant change despite
explicit support for recovery programmes.
It is difficult to escape the conclusion that operational
specificity was unwisely sacrificed in the interest of more efficiently spreading
the good news. The movement’s watchwords—voice, authenticity, process, settling
old scores and filing fresh grievances—proved ill-matched to the grind of institutional
sway and regulatory reform. Recovery had merit, morals and the tempered weight
of science behind it and so it sashayed into political battle unarmed. [ibid: 873]
Thus the second half of the paper looks
to try to address this lack by unpacking the notion of recovery in such a way
that it can be ‘operationalised’. Hopper’s suggestion is to understand recovery
on the lines of a capabilities approach. There seem to be two key elements to
this.
First, a capabilities approach
contrasts with an even (‘utilitarian’)distribution of resources by looking
instead at needs.
Instead of satisfaction or utility or some package of ‘primary
goods,’ Sen proposes that we consider not resources but rather the valued things
people are able to do or to be as a result of having them—the capabilities they
command. Actual welfare depends less on what I own or have access to than the
real opportunities open to me as a result. [ibid: 874]
Second, mental health and illness are
modelled on a two factor view of disability: on the one hand, original impairment (here,
psychiatric disorder) and on the other, the disability which is constituted by
the social reception and consequences of the impairment. Combined, this gives a
model of recovery on these lines:
A capabilities-informed ‘social recovery’ will speak to
citizenship as well as health. It will worry about what enables people to
thrive, not simply survive... Recovery asks not what such people should be
content with but what they should be capable of, and how that might be best
achieved and sustained. [ibid: 874]
As my colleague, Karen Newbigging,
pointed out, this gives a picture of recovery as not so much a model of
healthcare but as a meta-level theory into which healthcare slots as one thing
among others. Given the two-factor model, it also allows for a natural position
for a technical, biological psychiatry to address the ‘original impairment’.
That seems to be an interestingly conventional feature of his thinking. More
radically, one might think that the ontological status of the first factor was
derivative of the second. That is, one might think that there is no theory neutral set of original impairments. What is so deemed depends on social values.
Two other features of the way this
broad structure is elaborated are notable. First, and reflecting the criticism
in the first half of the paper, Hopper suggests that the capabilities version
of the recovery movement has to be operationalised if it is to be effective and
this requires some sort of universal, a priori list of human necessities:
Any application of capabilities must therefore first
define/defend a (full or partial) list of valued functionings..., or specify a
process for identifying/weighting them..., and then devise provisional means for
assessing real opportunities for achieving them (capabilities proper). [ibid: 876]
The obvious worry this raises in the
context of the history of mental healthcare is paternalism. Now, I think that that
is a price worth paying (cf my criticism of Fulford’s pure procedural version
of Values Based Practice) but others might not and Hopper does not seem to notice that this may
be an issue. Further, it may be in tension, at least, with one of the things
that he thinks will be on the list: the opportunity to exercise autonomy and agency.
Here he suggests, in effect, the right to make unwise decisions.
With respect to formal interventions, a capabilities- informed
approach to recovery would stress enhanced agency—not public safety, stable
placements or reliable program-participation. This means asking under what
circumstances exercising reasoned choice should be prized over foreseeable bad consequences
in one’s life. Can a poor choice, assessed in terms of compromised well-being,
be preferred if the foregone benefit could have been won only if imposed? [ibid:
877]
The tension is that the stress on
agency and autonomy and the right to make unwise decisions at the level of the
individual pulls against the idea that a policy maker might articulate a
universal list of what is good for people. Now it seems plausible on an
Aristotelian conception of flourishing, for example, that agency will be
important, will be on any such list, but if so the value of agency has to be
constrained by the other features of the list and vice versa.
This tension is present in a list of
potential difficulties towards the end of the paper with the suggestion that ‘Deprivation
and disgrace can so corrode one’s self worth that aspiration can be distorted,
initiative undercut and preferences deformed’ [ibid: 877]. That seems right and
suggests – correctly in my view – that there should be some element of
normative assessment of individuals’ values (I am that paternalistic!). One may
be wrong to value something. But Hopper continues: ‘Sensitive work will be
needed to recover that suppressed sense of injustice and reclaim lost possibility’
which suggests that he already knows that if anyone, ever, thought that their
mental healthcare had been good then they must be wrong. That seems overly
paternalistic to me.
All that said, there is something admirable, and rare, about a paper which explicitly addresses the underlying conceptual model of recovery. By connecting recovery to a two factor model of disability and then addressing the consequences of this for what people do and should value, Hopper provides a model which is distinct from a conventional biomedical model.
Hopper, K. (2007) ‘Rethinking social recovery in schizophrenia: What
a capabilities approach might offer’ Social Science & Medicine 65: 868–879
Subscribe to:
Posts (Atom)