A work in progress...
In a post a couple of years ago, I
expressed some
suspicion of Hannah Ginsborg’s conception of primitive normativity. If I
understand her, the idea is to locate a position which helps account for how
concepts can be learnt and is poised thus between a merely dispositional
account (which leaves too much of a gap still to be crossed to achieve full
conceptual mastery) and a fully conceptual grasp (which begs the question of
concepts can be learnt). The middle ground is a notion of ‘primitive
normativity’:
“primitive normativity”: very
roughly, normativity which does not depend on conformity to an antecedently
recognized rule. [ibid: 233]
‘Conformity to an antecedently recognized rule’ corresponds
to full blown conceptual normativity according to which:
the child says “42” after “40”
because she recognizes, although without being able to put that recognition
into words, that she has been adding two and that 40 plus two is 42. Her sense
of the appropriateness of what she is saying thus derives from her recognition
that it fits the rule she was following: a rule which she grasps, even though
she is unable to articulate it. [ibid: 238]
Primitive normativity involves less than that. But it
involves more than the merely reliable dispositional reactions of a suitable
trained parrot.
unlike the parrot, [the
child]... does not respond “blindly” to her circumstances. Even though she does
not say “42” as a result of having grasped the add-two rule, nor a fortiori of
having “seen” that 40 plus two is 42, she nonetheless “sees” her utterance of “42”
as appropriate to, or fitting, her circumstances. [ibid: 237]
So even though the child lacks full blown conceptual
mastery, she has a sense of appropriateness, fitting or belonging which merits
the label ‘normativity’. Ginsborg gives a second example of sorting coloured
objects before acquiring determinate colour concepts:
As she puts each green object in
the designated box, it is plausible that she does so with a sense that this is
the appropriate thing to do. She takes it that the green spoon “belongs” in the
box containing the previously sorted green things and that the blue spoon does
not, just as the child in the previous example takes 42 and not 43 to “belong” after
40 in the series of numerals. But her sense of the appropriateness of what she
is doing does not, at least on the face of it, depend on her taking what she is
doing to accord with a rule which she was following, for example, the rule that
she is to put all the green things in the same box. For her grasp of such a
rule would presuppose that she already possesses the concept green. [ibid: 235]
The objections to full blown conceptual normativity and
to dispositionalism are clear (which is not to say I agree with them). What is
less clear to me is just how primitive ‘primitive normativity’ is. My worry stems
from a potential difference between two comments Ginsborg makes:
1: ‘she lacked any conception of what her saying
“42” after “40” had in common with her having said “40” after “38”’ [ibid: 234
italics added]
and
2: ‘Rather, it seems plausible to imagine her insisting,
with no less conviction than a child who was able to cite the add-two rule,
that “42” was the right thing to say after “40”: that it “came next” in the
series, or “belonged” after 40, or “fit” what she had been doing previously’
[ibid: 234 italics added]
The former states that the counting child has no conception of what one move has in
common with a previous move. The second allows for the possibility of some conception that the next move fits or belongs (ie does have something in common) with the previous one in
context. The latter allows for a conception albeit a local one. I am unsure
which Ginsborg believes.
‘No conception’
primitive normativity
Before setting out why a local conception is a
satisfactory thing to hold to, it is worth seeing whether there is reason to
think Ginsborg believes in the more minimal version. One passage which might
prompt it runs:
The utterance, from her point of
view, is not appropriate to the context in virtue of its conforming to a
general rule which the context imposed on her, for example, the add-two rule.
Rather, she takes it to be appropriate to the context simpliciter, in a
way which does not depend for its coherence on the idea of an antecedently
applicable rule to which it conforms. [ibid: 234-5]
Now one way to interpret the phrase ‘antecedently
applicable rule’ is a context-independent specification of a rule. In the
context of a mathematical series, that is a plausible way of cashing out full blown
conceptual normativity. And hence its rejection might allow for a demonstratively
specified merely local conception of
the demands of a rule. But it might be taken to mean, and hence to rule out, any conception. If so, the context
imposes a sense of what move belongs with previous moves, of what next move is
right, independently of any conception the child has of what she is doing. The
way the quotation continues adds to this impression:
This is not to deny that the
normativity depends on any facts about the context, since the appropriateness
of “42” depends on her having recited that particular sequence of number words.
But it is to deny that her claim to the appropriateness of “42” depends on her
recognition of a rule imposed by the context in virtue of the relevant facts,
or a fortiori on her recognition of “42” as a correct application of the rule. [ibid:
235]
The picture is thus one in which facts about the context
external to the child’s conception of the demands of the rule make normative
demands. The context of having counted up to 40 makes saying ‘42’ appropriate
independently of her conception of what she is doing. ‘42’ belongs to what has
gone before, is normatively connected to it, but she does not recognise that
this is the demand that the rule makes.
A second paragraph provides a distinct argument for the
no conception view if that is wedded to the idea of a local conception of what
going on in the same way is.
the child’s recognition of
similarity is not sufficient to account for her taking herself to be going on
appropriately. She must not merely take herself to be going on the same way;
she must also take it that going on the same way is the appropriate thing to do
in the context, which is to say that she must grasp a rule with a content like go on the same way or do the same thing you were doing before.
We are thus left with the problem of how to account for her grasp of this rule...
[ibid: 240]
The argument is that grasp of what sameness comprises
(and I am going to suggest that this is merely expressible demonstratively as
going on like this) is insufficient
for knowing how to continue. One would need to grasp the further rule that one should go on in the same way, that this
is what the relevant normative demand is.
There is something to this. There seems little prospect
of factoring grasp of a rule into grasp of sameness plus grasp that sameness is
what one ought to aim at. As Wittgenstein stresses, sameness or agreement is
internal and relative to the particular rule. Thus grasp of the rule and grasp
of what agrees with it, what is relevantly the same in virtue of according with
the rule, goes hand in hand. But this point applies equally to what Ginsborg
does make explicit: that the child grasps that the next move fits, belongs or is appropriate
to the context. Those notions are equally insufficient for going on correctly.
(A rule could dictate that the next move should stand out from rather than
fitting what has gone before.)
Objections to ‘no
conception’ primitive normativity
An alternative:
local conception normativity