AAPP 24th Annual Meeting
The Biopsychosocial and Other Models for Psychiatry
SATURDAY and SUNDAY
MAY 5 and 6, 2012
THE CROWNE PLAZA HOTEL
INDEPENDENCE A
SECOND FLOOR
PHILADELPHIA, PA, USA
Program
Friday, 24 February 2012
Wednesday, 22 February 2012
Values Based Practice, Social Policy and the Service User identity
This is a first draft of a paper I am writing with my colleague David Morris, as the result of a chance coffee whilst banished from our building during a fire alarm/practice. We are both, in Bill Fulford's phrase 'critical friends' of VBP (very much more for it than against it) and this paper reflects that.
NB a later, better second draft is here.
Introduction
‘Values Based Practice’ (VBP) might be the name of any approach that paid due and serious attention to the role of values alongside facts in good healthcare. But it has also become the name of a particular approach to working with diverse values in healthcare pioneered by the psychiatrist and philosopher KWM (Bill) Fulford. In this paper, we will take it to mean the latter.
Values Based Practice and clinical decision making
VBP rejects both of these aspects of the traditional view. Values are implicated in diagnosis as well as treatment. And any moral principles to which we might appeal are insufficient to guide good practice. The arguments for the first element need not concern us in any detail here [see Thornton 2007: 62-73; Thornton 2011]. But they have to do with the idea that illness in general is an evaluative notion. Illness is bad for the sufferer and that notion of badness is essentially evaluative. (Thus VBP is committed to the failure of programmes to reduce the notion of illness to value-free biological notions such as proper function and it failure. But, first, there is grave doubt as to whether the pattern of explanation in which functions are deployed really is value-free [See Thornton 2000]. Second, even the foremost contemporary philosopher of psychiatry who defends the use of failure of function to capture the idea of disorder explicitly combines that with the value, harm, to analyse illness and disease [Wakefield 1992, 1999].)
As is familiar, these four, which do not derive from any single higher principle, can conflict. Beauchamp and Childress describe two methods for dealing with such conflicts: specification and balancing. Specification is a way of deriving more concrete guidance from the fairly abstract higher level principles. It ‘is a process of reducing the indeterminateness of abstract norms and providing them with action guiding content. For example, without further specification, do no harm is an all-too-bare starting point for thinking through problems, such as assisted suicide and euthanasia. It will not adequately guide action when norms conflict.’ [Beauchamp and Childress 2001: 16]
Neither balancing nor specification simply unpacks the content of the principles themselves. Nor, like deductive nomological explanation in the physical sciences, do they combine general principles with particular circumstances in a deductive argument. Both require an extra element of judgement. Thus even according to the Four Principles approach, the four principles are not sufficient for medical ethical judgement.
First, rather than aiming to arrive at the right outcome in a conflict, VBP aims instead at there being a good process. That is, it rejects the idea that a particular accommodation of values might be the right result in any particular context in favour of a method. Correctness, if it applies at all, applies to the method followed. Fulford summarises this idea thus: ‘conflicts of values are resolved primarily, not by reference to a rule prescribing a ‘right’ outcome, but by processes designed to support a balance of legitimately different perspectives (the ‘multi-perspective’ principle)’ [Fulford 2004: 206].
Despite these pointers, however, Values Based Practice is theoretically minimalist. That is not to say that it is not based on theoretical considerations. It draws heavily on Fulford’s analysis of the evaluative nature of diagnosis which in turn is based in the ordinary language analysis pioneered in Oxford in the 1950s and 1960s, especially Hare’s early work on the logical properties of value terms, in his Language of Morals [Fulford 1989; Hare 1952]. But that theoretical articulation is used to defend a theoretically-light approach to forming value judgements.
By contrast with what Fulford calls ‘quasi-legal medical ethics’ in which value judgements are derived from a rich body of principles or the equivalent of case law, VBP leaves them to a process of exploration, self- and other-knowledge and discussion. It accepts ‘dissensus’ as a likely outcome. It is a liberal approach to the values in question. Aside from the framework values, all and any values have equal merit prior to the process of local debate.
In clinical decision making, Values Based Practice can start from the particular patient and his or her clinical team. Thus the question of who is the patient or service user can, to a first approximation, be taken for granted prior to the application of VBP. But that is not true to anything like the same extent in cases to which VBP may be extended and applied: the investigation and evaluation of social policies concerning healthcare.
In the case of the application of Values Based Practice to a particular patient and their pre-existing clinical team, the question: who is the service user is not, typically, a pressing problem. But what of the case of the development of new health policies?
This is not to say that such a question is unanswerable. But answering it will involve assessing the competing claims of different potential groups for priority. Since that is an evaluative (as well as a factual) matter it might have been thought that it could be settled by an application of Values Based Practice. But it turns out that VBP presupposes a prior answer to it. In other words, the question of service user identity is an evaluative matter which, whilst vital, cannot be addressed by VBP as it is applied to clinical decision making.
Recognising that there is a difference between the two cases is however helpful. In the clinical case, the question of identifying the service user identity can be taken for granted for practical, contingent reasons. That is not true of the policy case. But it might be assumed that identifying the service users in the latter case can be modelled on the former through a slippage between the idea of identifying service users to the idea of a service user identity. So the relevant service users for a proposed mental health policy might be thought to be the community of service users, those who take to on that as their identity.
There are, however, reasons to be wary of the very idea of a service user identity which we will now outline.
The contingent perils of a service user identity
First, the very idea of a service user identity, based on shared experience could, ironically, limit relationships with other disadvantaged communities whose own complementary claims could be an resource. To privilege the collective voice of common interest over other perspectives and communities may encourage such communities to turn inwards.
Second, it circumscribes the context within which individual capabilities can be understood and appreciated. Behind the case for equity of opportunity is an implicit argument for the recognition of capability. The right to participate is driven by an assertion of personal capability to participate. A categorical approach to defining community may place limits on the way in which its members and their diverse capabilities, both individual and shared, will be expressed and perceived externally, thereby limiting the effect of that aspect of empowerment concerned with the proper recognition of what people can do. This links to the third problem.
Fourth, the potential for individual recovery, whether defined at the level of the individual or at a population level, is usually calibrated against an assessment of the response of other people. For example, how successful a person with a mental illness might be in holding down a job in an open plan office is likely to depend on an assessment made of the anticipated or actual response of office colleagues (‘the work community’), while policy on employment for people with mental health problems is likely to take this into account, deploying study data (or not!) in which examples of such individual experience is aggregated as an evidence base for the existence, and therefore policy relevance, of stigma and discrimination as factors to be considered in service model development. It is important therefore to give these external social accounts some descriptive weighting in order to advance social recovery prospects and, to the extent that such discourse is conducted within the conceptual framework of ‘the community’ (which is the case for policy and practice in public mental health as well as that for services), it is important to provide for an understanding of community perspectives associated with ‘the other’ that has some equivalence to those associated with that of illness experience.
Service user centrality and theoretical minimalism
Bibliography
Beauchamp, T.L. and Childress, J.F. (2001) Principles of Biomedical Ethics Oxford: Oxford University Press
Fulford, K.W.M. (1989) Moral Theory and Medical Practice Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
Fulford, K.W.M. (2004) Ten Principles of Values-Based Medicine. in Radden, J. (ed) The Philosophy of Psychiatry: A Companion New York: Oxford University Press, 205-34
Hare, R.M. (1952) The Language of Morals Oxford: Oxford University Press
Thornton, T. (2000) ‘Mental Illness and Reductionism: Can Functions be Naturalized?’ Philosophy, Psychiatry and Psychology 7: 67-76
Thornton, T. (2006) Judgement and the role of the metaphysics of values in medical ethics. Journal of Medical Ethics, 32, 365-370
Thornton, T. (2007) Essential Philosophy of Psychiatry Oxford: Oxford University Press
Thornton, T. (2011) Radical liberal values based practice’ Journal of Evaluation in Clinical Practice 17: 988-91
Wakefield , J.C. (1992) ‘The Concept of Mental
Disorder: On the Boundary Between Biological Facts and Social Values’ American Psychologist 47: 373-88
Wakefield, J.C. (1999) Mental disorder as a black box essentialist concept. Journal of Abnormal Psychology 108: 465-472
NB a later, better second draft is here.
Introduction
‘Values Based Practice’ (VBP) might be the name of any approach that paid due and serious attention to the role of values alongside facts in good healthcare. But it has also become the name of a particular approach to working with diverse values in healthcare pioneered by the psychiatrist and philosopher KWM (Bill) Fulford. In this paper, we will take it to mean the latter.
Although drawing on a substantial philosophically framework, VBP
is, itself in one key respect, theoretically minimalist. That is, aside from
some framework values, the violation of which would undermine the very
possibility of VBP, the work of managing diverse values is not determined or
dictated by antecedent principles. Its ‘principles’ are more pointers or
reminders. Nor is it even driven by the goal or telos of a right outcome but is
instead guided by the idea of following a good process. The task of managing a
legitimate diversity of values is left to a process of discussion by those who
have a stake in the outcome, a discussion the shape of which is left
deliberately open-ended. Whilst there are some pointers to guide the debate,
there are few ground rules.
But whilst it is plausible that the application of VBP to
clinical decisions with particular identified patients or health service users,
and a particular team of health professionals provided by the contingent
circumstances of care, can be theoretically minimalist (though whether it can
be as minimalist as it is taken by Fulford to be is open to question [see
Thornton 2011]) its application to policy development cannot escape some
substantive antecedent commitments.
A key question concerns the identity of service users in the
context of policy development. By contrast with the case of clinical decision
making, this identity cannot be taken for granted. But ‘not taking it for
granted’ means, in this case, that it cannot be settled prior to some judgements about relevant values, judgements thus
prior to and outside the application of VBP. At the same time, we will also
caution against conceiving of the service user identity in the policy case on
the model of that of clinical decision making. At the risk of slipping into
jargon: the service user identity should not be thought of essentially, or
exclusively. It is an identity relative to context.
Values Based Practice and clinical decision making
Values Based Practice stands in opposition to an implicit or
inchoate traditional view of the relation of facts and values in medical care. On this traditional
view, medical diagnosis is a matter of getting the facts right independent of
any values. Values come
into play in guiding – alongside good evidence based medicine – treatment and
management. And when they do, they are codified in a set of principles, a
proper understanding of which form a kind of moral calculus.
VBP rejects both of these aspects of the traditional view. Values are implicated in diagnosis as well as treatment. And any moral principles to which we might appeal are insufficient to guide good practice. The arguments for the first element need not concern us in any detail here [see Thornton 2007: 62-73; Thornton 2011]. But they have to do with the idea that illness in general is an evaluative notion. Illness is bad for the sufferer and that notion of badness is essentially evaluative. (Thus VBP is committed to the failure of programmes to reduce the notion of illness to value-free biological notions such as proper function and it failure. But, first, there is grave doubt as to whether the pattern of explanation in which functions are deployed really is value-free [See Thornton 2000]. Second, even the foremost contemporary philosopher of psychiatry who defends the use of failure of function to capture the idea of disorder explicitly combines that with the value, harm, to analyse illness and disease [Wakefield 1992, 1999].)
The second step to articulate
Values Based Practice is the rejection of both the sufficiency and the
fundamental importance of moral principles in guiding medical practice. The
first follows from a feature which is present even in Tom
Beauchamp and James Childress’s attempt to relate medical ethical
reasoning to a set of principles [Beauchamp and Childress 2001].
Principles of Biomedical sets
out four general principles to guide medical ethical reasoning: autonomy, beneficence, non maleficence and justice.
As is familiar, these four, which do not derive from any single higher principle, can conflict. Beauchamp and Childress describe two methods for dealing with such conflicts: specification and balancing. Specification is a way of deriving more concrete guidance from the fairly abstract higher level principles. It ‘is a process of reducing the indeterminateness of abstract norms and providing them with action guiding content. For example, without further specification, do no harm is an all-too-bare starting point for thinking through problems, such as assisted suicide and euthanasia. It will not adequately guide action when norms conflict.’ [Beauchamp and Childress 2001: 16]
Balancing and complements
specification thus: ‘Specification
entails a substantive refinement of the range and scope of norms, whereas
balancing consists of deliberation and judgement about the relative weights or
strengths of norms. Balancing is especially important for reaching judgements
in individual cases.’ [Beauchamp and Childress 2001: 18]
Neither balancing nor specification simply unpacks the content of the principles themselves. Nor, like deductive nomological explanation in the physical sciences, do they combine general principles with particular circumstances in a deductive argument. Both require an extra element of judgement. Thus even according to the Four Principles approach, the four principles are not sufficient for medical ethical judgement.
Values Based Practice goes
further than this, however. Although it concedes that there can be sufficient
agreement about some values that they can codified to provide the basis for
ethical codes and guidelines and other agreed elements for any thinking
about healthcare, these remain just a small
part of the values that have to be taken account of in guiding medical practice
which include individual preferences, desires, wishes, firmly held faith and
convictions and so forth.
By stressing this
multiplicity, it stresses the standing possibility of disagreements and clashes
in thinking about particular circumstances. But if values are ubiquitous
and if, agreed framework aside, disagreement is both to be expected and
legitimate, how can the process of assessing the competing ‘pulls’ of different
values be managed? To repeat, within the framework, guidance by principles is
of limited use. There are three key suggestions.
First, rather than aiming to arrive at the right outcome in a conflict, VBP aims instead at there being a good process. That is, it rejects the idea that a particular accommodation of values might be the right result in any particular context in favour of a method. Correctness, if it applies at all, applies to the method followed. Fulford summarises this idea thus: ‘conflicts of values are resolved primarily, not by reference to a rule prescribing a ‘right’ outcome, but by processes designed to support a balance of legitimately different perspectives (the ‘multi-perspective’ principle)’ [Fulford 2004: 206].
Second, ‘communication skills
have a substantive rather than (as in quasi-legal ethics) a merely executive
role in clinical decision-making (the ‘how it’s done’ principle)’ [ibid: 206].
This again reflects the idea that correctness attaches not to an endpoint but to
a process. Thus there is equal stress on methods of raising awareness of values
by attention to language use (the ‘values-blindness’ principle) and for
improving knowledge of other people’s values (the ‘values-myopia’ principle).
Fulford characterises VBP
using ten principles or pointers.
Ten Principles of Values Based
Practice
1: All decisions stand on two
feet, on values as well as on facts, including decisions about diagnosis (the ‘two
feet’ principle)
2: We tend to notice values
only when they are diverse or conflicting and hence are likely to be
problematic (the ‘squeaky wheel’ principle)
3: Scientific progress, in
opening up choices, is increasingly bringing the full diversity of human values
into play in all areas of healthcare (the ‘science driven’ principle)
4: VBP’s ‘first call’ for
information is the perspective of the patient or patient group concerned in a
given decision (the ‘patient-perspective’ principle)
5: In VBP, conflicts of values
are resolved primarily, not by reference to a rule prescribing a ‘right’
outcome, but by processes designed to support a balance of legitimately
different perspectives (the ‘multi-perspective’ principle)
6: Careful attention to
language use in a given context is one of a range of powerful methods for
raising awareness of values (the ‘values-blindness’ principle)
7: A rich resource of both
empirical and philosophical methods is available for improving our knowledge of
other people’s values (the ‘values-myopia’ principle)
8: Ethical Reasoning is
employed in VBP primarily to explore differences of values, not, as in
quasi-legal bioethics, to determine ‘what is right’ (the ‘space of values’
principle)
9: In VBP, communication
skills have a substantive rather than (as in quasi-legal ethics) a merely
executive role in clinical decision-making (the ‘how it’s done’ principle)
10: VBP, although involving a
partnership with ethicists and lawyers (equivalent to the partnership with
scientists and statisticians in EBM), puts decision-making back where it
belongs, with users and providers at the clinical coal-face (the ‘who decides’
principle)
Despite these pointers, however, Values Based Practice is theoretically minimalist. That is not to say that it is not based on theoretical considerations. It draws heavily on Fulford’s analysis of the evaluative nature of diagnosis which in turn is based in the ordinary language analysis pioneered in Oxford in the 1950s and 1960s, especially Hare’s early work on the logical properties of value terms, in his Language of Morals [Fulford 1989; Hare 1952]. But that theoretical articulation is used to defend a theoretically-light approach to forming value judgements.
By contrast with what Fulford calls ‘quasi-legal medical ethics’ in which value judgements are derived from a rich body of principles or the equivalent of case law, VBP leaves them to a process of exploration, self- and other-knowledge and discussion. It accepts ‘dissensus’ as a likely outcome. It is a liberal approach to the values in question. Aside from the framework values, all and any values have equal merit prior to the process of local debate.
But that theoretically minimalism is made possible in part by
taking one thing for granted. As the fourth pointer says: VBP’s ‘first call’ for information is the
perspective of the patient or patient group concerned in a given decision (the ‘patient-perspective’
principle). That principle militates against a slippage of discussion into a
paternalist imposition of values on, or against, the patient or service user. But
it assumes that the question of who is the patient or service user can be
decided independently of the application of VBP to value judgements. This is a
reasonable assumption in the case of clinical decision making where the identities
of patients, clinicians and other members of a healthcare team are fixed by
local contingencies.
In clinical decision making, Values Based Practice can start from the particular patient and his or her clinical team. Thus the question of who is the patient or service user can, to a first approximation, be taken for granted prior to the application of VBP. But that is not true to anything like the same extent in cases to which VBP may be extended and applied: the investigation and evaluation of social policies concerning healthcare.
Values based practice, social
policy and service user identity: the underlying logic
In the case of the application of Values Based Practice to a particular patient and their pre-existing clinical team, the question: who is the service user is not, typically, a pressing problem. But what of the case of the development of new health policies?
The problem in a nutshell is
this. Any practical proposed health or social care policy would have a number
of effects or consequences, both positive and negative. A policy designed to
reach members of a community unwilling to report their mental health problems,
for example, might have such people as its service users. But if it addressed
them by addressing families, then healthy family members might also be count as
service users. And if the aim were to improve social inclusion within the
community, other members of the community might count as service users. Given
that VBP prioritises the ‘patient or patient group concerned in a given
decision (the ‘patient-perspective’ principle)’ this raises the question: who
should count as the patient or service user in such a case?
This is not to say that such a question is unanswerable. But answering it will involve assessing the competing claims of different potential groups for priority. Since that is an evaluative (as well as a factual) matter it might have been thought that it could be settled by an application of Values Based Practice. But it turns out that VBP presupposes a prior answer to it. In other words, the question of service user identity is an evaluative matter which, whilst vital, cannot be addressed by VBP as it is applied to clinical decision making.
Recognising that there is a difference between the two cases is however helpful. In the clinical case, the question of identifying the service user identity can be taken for granted for practical, contingent reasons. That is not true of the policy case. But it might be assumed that identifying the service users in the latter case can be modelled on the former through a slippage between the idea of identifying service users to the idea of a service user identity. So the relevant service users for a proposed mental health policy might be thought to be the community of service users, those who take to on that as their identity.
There are, however, reasons to be wary of the very idea of a service user identity which we will now outline.
The contingent perils of a service user identity
We will outline four reasons to be cautious of the idea that a
community of service users can be picked out through a service user identity.
First, the very idea of a service user identity, based on shared experience could, ironically, limit relationships with other disadvantaged communities whose own complementary claims could be an resource. To privilege the collective voice of common interest over other perspectives and communities may encourage such communities to turn inwards.
Second, it circumscribes the context within which individual capabilities can be understood and appreciated. Behind the case for equity of opportunity is an implicit argument for the recognition of capability. The right to participate is driven by an assertion of personal capability to participate. A categorical approach to defining community may place limits on the way in which its members and their diverse capabilities, both individual and shared, will be expressed and perceived externally, thereby limiting the effect of that aspect of empowerment concerned with the proper recognition of what people can do. This links to the third problem.
Third, in
practice, the right to be equally valued irrespective of difference is likely
to be realised only in a social context in which the capabilities of people
with disability are recognised and the potential for defining people
principally in terms of disability are eradicated. The positive perception of
disability necessary to actions that support empowerment are associated with
the idea that the nature and value of an individual’s activity should be seen
as a function of their multiple identity. A service response to the needs of
people with disability which incorporates their role as citizens with
contributory assets alongside that of service users with needs, is conditional
on the notion of multiple identity being understood by public agencies. This
understanding may not be best served by retaining, as the basis for service
organisation, a model of community characterised by a singular definition of
membership especially in a service environment governed by a contemporary
concern with community health and civic engagement.
Fourth, the potential for individual recovery, whether defined at the level of the individual or at a population level, is usually calibrated against an assessment of the response of other people. For example, how successful a person with a mental illness might be in holding down a job in an open plan office is likely to depend on an assessment made of the anticipated or actual response of office colleagues (‘the work community’), while policy on employment for people with mental health problems is likely to take this into account, deploying study data (or not!) in which examples of such individual experience is aggregated as an evidence base for the existence, and therefore policy relevance, of stigma and discrimination as factors to be considered in service model development. It is important therefore to give these external social accounts some descriptive weighting in order to advance social recovery prospects and, to the extent that such discourse is conducted within the conceptual framework of ‘the community’ (which is the case for policy and practice in public mental health as well as that for services), it is important to provide for an understanding of community perspectives associated with ‘the other’ that has some equivalence to those associated with that of illness experience.
Service user centrality and theoretical minimalism
As we outlined in the first section, when Values-Based Practice
is applied to individual clinical cases, it is theoretically minimalist. With
the parties to a clinical decisions identified, VBP imposes a background of
shared values – necessary for it to function at all – but then leaves the
management of rational and legitimate disagreement about values to a discussion
in which highlighting the values involved, including hidden and implicit values
and communication skills play a central role. By adopting a form of theoretical
minimalism, VBP can avoid having to settle contentious global debates about
competing moral theories and approaches. Providing that there is sufficient
agreement about framework values, VBP can leave the discussion of competing
values to a local context. The particular participants can examine their values
relevant for the particular decisions concerned.
Such discussion is not, however, entirely free. A safeguard
against paternalism is the ‘patient-perspective’
principle: the ‘first call’ for information is the perspective of the patient.
But, as we have argued, the combination of this principle and theoretical
minimalism cannot be carried over in to the context of policy development.
Identifying the claims of groups to count as service users, to count as having
more say than others, cannot be taken for granted. If not, it must itself be
subject to a value-laden debate and judgement. If VBP is identified with a
minimalism, then this issue cannot be settled by VBP alone. If it is not so identified,
then the application of VBP to policy debate will call for a more structured
approach to weighing the opinions and values of those who may be affected. The
cost of the application is giving up minimalism. Some values will have more
values than others.
There is, however, a benefit from this cost. In the previous
section, we drew attention to some contingent but typical dangers from
approaching the question of the identity of service users in the policy case
with the same simple mindedness which works for the clinical case. If one
thinks of service users as those picked out by having a service user identity –
as a particular community fixed prior to potential policy developments – then
this will encourage the isolation and permanence of that community. But if
instead, identifying the service user community or communities depends on the
policy under debate and its particular consequences, these dangers can be
diminished.
To count as a service user – relative to a particular policy –
will depend on fitting a role, or characteristic. This follows from the idea
that so counting will flow from an argument
which will have to be couched in general terms such as why having such and such
a role puts one in a position to have an expertise in so and so. Thus a sufferer
from a mental illness may also be a tax paying citizen, a family member, a
carer, a member of a particular ethnic grouping etc. Thus the individual can
properly count as a member of any number of differing communities relevant to a
policy initiative and thus merit a number of different voices.
Bibliography
Beauchamp, T.L. and Childress, J.F. (2001) Principles of Biomedical Ethics Oxford: Oxford University Press
Fulford, K.W.M. (1989) Moral Theory and Medical Practice Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
Fulford, K.W.M. (2004) Ten Principles of Values-Based Medicine. in Radden, J. (ed) The Philosophy of Psychiatry: A Companion New York: Oxford University Press, 205-34
Hare, R.M. (1952) The Language of Morals Oxford: Oxford University Press
Thornton, T. (2000) ‘Mental Illness and Reductionism: Can Functions be Naturalized?’ Philosophy, Psychiatry and Psychology 7: 67-76
Thornton, T. (2006) Judgement and the role of the metaphysics of values in medical ethics. Journal of Medical Ethics, 32, 365-370
Thornton, T. (2007) Essential Philosophy of Psychiatry Oxford: Oxford University Press
Thornton, T. (2011) Radical liberal values based practice’ Journal of Evaluation in Clinical Practice 17: 988-91
Wakefield, J.C. (1999) Mental disorder as a black box essentialist concept. Journal of Abnormal Psychology 108: 465-472
Friday, 17 February 2012
A temporary entry on concepts, propositions, truth and occasions
In ‘Meaning’s role in truth’, Charles Travis says that whilst the
words uttered impose a condition on truth, different occasions impose different
standards for satisfying that condition. That way of putting makes it seem that
there is always the same condition (fixed by the albeit plastic meaning of the
words involved in expressing it) and the occasion of its utterance provides a
different standard (though not merely weaker and stronger, of course) for it to
count as met.
It would be helpful to shed more light on quite how what
is fixed – for example by word meaning – and what varies, according to occasions
of utterance, is apportioned in Travis’ picture.
Here is one such
indication. In ‘To represent as so’, Travis criticises one element of Frege’s
thinking.
For Frege, a concept is a function, namely, one from
objects to truth values. (See Frege 1891.) If words ‘Sid grunts’ decompose into
an element ‘Sid’, which names an object, and an element ‘grunts’, which names a
function from objects to truth-values, then the whole, ‘Sid grunts’, names the
value of that function for a certain argument, namely, Sid. Which is to say
that it names a truth-value: true if Sid grunts, false if he does not. Which is
to say that for parts jointly to play these roles is, ipso facto, for
them to decide a unique and determinate truth condition for their whole. Mutatis
mutandis for propositions, of which words ‘Sid grunts’ could be but one instance,
or expression. [Travis 2011: 172]
According to this view, if an element in a
proposition (which has pride of place in both Frege’s and Wittgenstein’s
thinking) has the role of naming an object or naming a concept its contribution
to the truth condition and thus truth value of the whole is fixed by that alone.
Inspired by the later Wittgenstein’s deployment of
language games, Travis considers two different contexts for the sentence ‘The room
is dark’. In one, it is used to say that books cannot be found by vision alone.
In the other, it indicates that undeveloped film can be removed from a
canister.
One might correctly say of either game that in it ‘is
dark’ names (speaks of) being dark. But the role it plays in naming this
differs from the one game to the other. In the one game, but not the other, it
contributes to a condition on being as said which is not satisfied if, where
whether to remove film turns on whether the room is dark, removing film is not
the thing to do. So if a move consists (on an analysis) of parts, for each of which
there is a such-and-such it names, those facts about the move are compatible
with any of indefinitely many mutually exclusive conditions on correctness
(answers to the question when things would be as thus said). [ibid: 173]
So if we think – with Frege – of words naming objects and
concepts, still a suitable combination of objects and concepts does not fix the
condition under which the result is true, contra the earlier summary of Frege.
That words name such-and-such determines no unique contribution
which is that which such words make to conditions on the correctness of the
whole they thus are part of. Such is just part of what naming is. It
holds equally for naming in the context of a move in a language game, and
naming in the context of a proposition. The fact of my speaking of being dark
is compatible with my saying any of many things in, and by, doing so. There are
many different things, each of which being dark may, sometimes correctly, be
taken to be (or come to). Being dark admits of understandings. [ibid: 173]
So the fact that words name such and such is fixed across occasions but its role in the truth of the whole varies between occasions of utterance. Returning to the earlier truism, Travis suggests that the following is the correct thing to say:
It is on an application of a concept to an object,
on an occasion, that one says the object to be thus and so. The rest of the
truism then holds. The concept as such admits of many applications, each
excluding others. So it alone cannot assign an object, in being as it is, a
truth value. [ibid: 173]
Sticking with the case of the room being dark, it seems
that the same concept is named by ‘dark’ in the different language games, but
it has a different application. The concept remains the same across occasions,
but its application not, and it is the application which matters to truth. The
same concept, I think, admits of ‘understandings’,
which correspond to the fine grained applications.
I think that the same applies to another Travis phrase for part of the
conceptual: ‘a way for things to be’.
What of propositions? These could be common between
different occasions but with different applications. Or they could be fine
grained: distinct between occasions. But given the connection between propositions
and truth, and given the connection between occasions of utterance and the truth
of sentences, propositions look to be fine grained (unlike concepts). (Cf also ‘A proposition makes a demand on the world: to decide, in being as it
is, the proposition’s fate—true or false. The proposition fixes a way for the
world to decide this—if the proposition is that the setting sun is red, then
what about the world would make this so or not.’ [ibid: 218]. This, I think, is evidence for my interpretation.)
There’s an added complication in that Travis is using
Wittgenstein to correct Frege and so it’s hard to know how much is invested in
preserving the idea of propositions rather than exploring word use in language
games. But in ‘The proposition’s progress’ there is both a clear suggestion that they
still find a place in Travis’ own approach and on the above question:
Propositions are one device for carving up
exposure to risk. Language games are another. Such games are used in the Investigations
to make a particular point, as above. This is not to banish the notion proposition.
In suitable circumstances I may say to you, ‘Pia said that there is wine on the
rug’, where this admits the response, ‘And is there?’. We may then go on to
discuss ‘the proposition that there is wine on the rug’. What proposition is
this? When would it be true? I mentioned it in words ‘there is wine on the
rug’. Things would be as they are according to that proposition when they would
be as those words speak of things being. When that would be is fixed by the
operation of parochial equipment on my words in just the way described,
above, for Pia’s. The above model of representing finds just this application here.
Such a proposition, one might say, is what it is to us. Nor does it thereby
speak of a way for things to be which admits of no divergent understandings.
(Cf. §§429-465.) [Travis 2011: 215]
The one thing which is confusing here is the last line.
It almost sounds as though the proposition admits of divergent understandings.
But my hunch is that different propositions are the results of divergent understandings of utterances.
Travis, C. (2011) ‘The proposition’s progress’ in Objectivity and the Parochial, Oxford:
Oxford University Press pp 193-228
Travis, C. (2011) ‘To represent as so’ in Objectivity and the Parochial, Oxford:
Oxford University Press pp 165-192
Wednesday, 15 February 2012
Innocence in Travis’ ‘Frege’s target’
I hope that setting out my own stumbling reading of Charles Travis motivates others to do rather better. ‘Frege’s target’ concerns knowledge of grammar a la Chomsky and McDowell’s account of knowledge which requires having a particular kind of mind (such as knowledge of other’s meanings and of moral value or the good life). Both general issues are approached via a criticism of empiricism which would make such knowledge impossible (and thus instead has to force it into a reductionist mould or deny that the world contains as many facts as we might have supposed).
As anti-empiricists, Chomsky and McDowell differ, however, in that whilst both think that knowledge (more than which empiricists would allow) requires having a particular kind of mind or subjectivity, the subject matter for Chomsky can be allowed to depend on, or itself be shaped by, that subjectivity. McDowell cannot allow that and this presents a prima facie problem. How can it be that the truths a thinker thinks might depend on features of their subjectivity without collapsing into a crass subjectivism? The answer, you won’t be surprised to hear, is a form of occasionalism.
In passing the points that characterise empiricism here are these:
[F]irst of all, a position arrived at a priori. It’s guiding notion, put one way, is that we are universal thinkers: we enjoy no cognitive capacities, so see nothing of the world, that would not be shared by any thinker with our sensory sensitivity to the stimuli that impinge on us (such things as light, sound, pressure).
Second, for a given domain, the empiricist will claim to identify those procedures, or abilities, which are the knowledge-yielding ones with respect to that domain. What these are is, from the empiricist perspective, something to be arrived at a priori. They will be just those capacities enjoyed by any thinker at all with relevant sensory sensitivities.
Third, the empiricist will hold that we can know a fact in the relevant domain only where that fact is provable, or ascertainable (with sufficient certainty) from privileged facts by application of the specified knowledge-yielding procedures.
Fourth, an empiricist may claim that there are facts in the relevant domain only insofar as these are derivable from privileged facts according to the principles defining the correct operation of those knowledge-yielding procedures. Typically, such an empiricist will hold that the facts in the chosen domain are far fewer, and less interesting, than we would have supposed. [Travis 314-7]
This is initially a surprising way of describing empiricism insofar as Epistemology and Metaphysics 101 goes. But the centrality of experience of the traditional Ep&Met view has to be fleshed out with some substance and Travis’ account dovetails with Quine whose views of knowledge of language is one of the two key foci of the paper and is a helpful foil to McDowell’s position
So back with the question raised above: How can it be that the truths a thinker thinks might depend on features of their subjectivity without collapsing into a crass subjectivism? I’ll drop some numbers into the quote of how the problem is set up.
Trivially, a statement is true just when things are the way they are according to it. That suggests, innocently enough, that a statement’s truth depends on precisely two factors [1]: first, how things are according to it; and, second, how things are. Innocence ends if one supposes that one can specify how things are according to a statement—which way it speaks of things as being—in such a way that the truth of any statement which speaks of things as that way can depend only on whether that is, in fact, a way things are. [2] Let P be a way a statement might thus represent things. Then, accepting that idea, [3] we may still innocently allow that the way given thinkers think decides whether some one of their statements stated that P, or, say, that Q, where that is another such way for a statement to represent things.
[4] But one cannot, accepting this idea, allow that, where a statement spoke of things as being P, whether it thus stated truth depends on how a particular (sort of) thinker thinks. [5] For what thinkers could thus decide, in thinking as they do could only be, within this framework, how things were: whether that which is so according to any statement which states P is so. That would be mind-dependence of the worst sort. Yet, with the end of innocence in place, anti-empiricism is under pressure to say just that. [6] For, given the role it assigns to sensibilities, it seems, where thinkers think in terms of, say, things being chairs or not, still, for all that, whether things are as they say (on some occasion) in saying such-and-such to be a chair depends in further ways on how they are designed, or equipped, to think. [ibid: 377-8]
So 1 is innocent: a statement’s truth depends on the two factors one would expect. 2 introduces an idea. If there is some slippage between a statement and how it might represent things, so if there is a way of thinking of the statement without appeal to the occasion of its use, we might label one way things might be P. And it remains innocent that what makes P what a statement states rather than Q a matter for features of the speaker.
So the problem comes with 4. ‘But one cannot... allow that, where a statement spoke of things as being P, whether it thus stated truth depends on how a particular (sort of) thinker thinks.’
But why would we? We’ve already allowed those features of subjectivity to fix whether it was P or Q stated in a given statement. Thereafter, why are we not back with the innocence of 1? The answer is 6: ‘it seems, where thinkers think in terms of, say, things being chairs or not, still, for all that, whether things are as they say (on some occasion) in saying such-and-such to be a chair depends in further ways on how they are designed, or equipped, to think.’
At this point I can’t help thinking that if we’ve bought into the significance of occasionalism, its need at this point might seem obvious. But I’m not there yet. A little earlier we have this helpful vignette:
Sid buys a DIY chair kit. On bringing it home he discovers that it is much more difficult to assemble than he had imagined. It remains a neatly stacked pile of chair parts in his spare room. One day, someone, pointing at the pile, asks, ‘What’s that?’ ‘It’s a chair’, Sid replies, ‘I just haven’t got around to assembling it yet.’ On a later occasion, Sid and Pia, with guests, find themselves a chair short for dinner. ‘There’s a chair in the spare room’, Sid says helpfully. But there is still only the pile. Recognisably, Sid spoke truly the first time, falsely the second. It just takes a different way of thinking of being a chair to see the truth of that first thing from the way it takes to see the falsehood of the second. Such contrasting ways of thinking are a common everyday part of our way of dealing with the world. [ibid: 336]
Given our understanding of the requirements of a chair in a hurry at a dinner party, the chair kit is not a chair. It is not true to say that there is a chair, on that understanding, in the spare room. If this is described sufficiently to explain – in yet another context – so that Sid’s comment, and its falsity, is clear to an audience, could that articulation of the content of the utterance not be called say P by contrast with the Q of the first understanding (where chair as kit is fine)? With that in place, why can’t we say 3 again? I’m not getting the problem. I would be much less puzzled if the very idea of labelling understandings as P and Q were supposed to be the end of innocence (though, in a context, occasionalism should not threaten mere labelling). But the key link seems dark. I will press on with the paper on psychologism and see whether it helps.
Travis, C. (2002) ‘Frege’s target’ Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplement 51: 305-343
Thursday, 9 February 2012
An aspect of Travis’ ‘Meaning’s role in truth’
What words mean imposes a condition on their saying, on a
speaking, what is so. Different occasions impose different standards for
satisfying that condition. Something about what truth is makes occasions matter
to such standards. Deflationism cannot recognize such elements in truth. [Travis
1996: 461]
If I follow, the picture is something like this. Word
meaning exerts a general constraint on what one can say in using them. So, for example, because
of its meaning, the word ‘round’ means round and utterances made using it will
speak of being round.
The words “is round”, in meaning what they do, speak of
being round. In fact, I suggest, for them to speak of that is just for them to
mean what they do. For English words to speak of being round comes to just
this. If you use them as meaning what they do, you will thereby speak of being
round. At least, on any occasion of your so speaking, that is something you
would then be doing. So if you want to speak of being round, e.g., so as to
call something round, or describe it as round, a way of achieving your aim in
speaking normal English is to speak the words “is round” (in a suitable
construction). [ibid: 455]
But that is only part of the story because of
occasionalism. The constraint that meaning imposes does not itself determine
the truth condition of an utterance in such a way as to connect to a bit of the
world. (I wonder whether the constraint meaning imposes would be enough to
state correct instances of the T-schema. But if so, such instances would still
leave open how or when the conditions described on the right hand side were realised.)
Consider the sentence “The ball is round”, and two cases
of its use. Case A: What shape do squash balls assume on rebound? Pia
hits a decent stroke; Jones watches. “The ball is round”, she says at the
crucial moment. Wrong. It has deformed into an ovoid. Jones did not say the
ball to be as it was, so spoke falsely. Case B: Fiona has never seen
squash played. From her present vantage point the ball seems a constant blur.
“What shape is that ball?”, she asks. “The ball is round”, Alf replies; truly,
since that it is the sort of ball a squash ball (and this one) is. It is not,
e.g., like a very small rugby ball. [ibid: 454]
So whether the sentence is true of a particular ball at a
particular time depends on something in addition to the meaning of the words.
It depends on the occasion of its use. In the summary quote with which I began,
Travis puts this point by saying that whilst the words uttered impose a
condition on truth, different occasions impose different standards for
satisfying that condition. That way of putting makes it seem that there is
always the same condition (that fixed by essentially plastic meaning) and the
occasion provides a different standard (though not merely weaker and stronger,
of course) for it to count as met. This may be deliberate for a reason I’ll
mention shortly.
Given occasionalism, it is not surprising that to know
what the conditions are that are needed for an utterance to be true depend on
the occasion of the utterance (recall the two squash ball cases). But Travis
thinks that this undermines deflationism about truth and it is not immediately
obvious why this might be so. The heart of deflationism is that instances of
the T schema (or an equivalent with propositions) captures all there is to
truth aside from issues of compendious endorsement and such like. So given occasionalism,
one might think that the plasticity of meaning stops such instances being very
helpful because the condition stated on the right hand side, is fixed only on
an occasion-relative understanding. But then, one might modify the deployment
of the T-schema to say that the sentence named on the left hand side, on a
particular occasion-relative understanding, is true on the condition set out by
a sentence used on the right hand side on the same occasion-relative
understanding. That might still serve the purposes of deflationism. So we’d need
more of an argument. But Travis offers more. He heads off this thought
(connecting to a proposition-based deflationism) which perhaps is the reason
for the way he approaches what is fixed and what varied mentioned above.
One might further think: which understanding words bear
depends on the circumstances of their speaking; when things would be as said to
be on a given understanding does not. Understandings, so conceived, extract content
from circumstances. Circumstances play no further role in determining conditions
for truth. Deflationism, and its use of “proposition”, depend on exactly that
idea... [ibid: 460]
So the idea Travis rejects takes the work of occasions to
be done once an understanding of a utterance has fixed the claim it makes about
the world. Once that is fixed, nothing more is needed to fix how the world must
be for it to be true, or not be for it to be false. That might support deflationism. But it is not Travis’
picture:
But here is another picture. Understanding requires
sensitivity. Understanding words consists, in part, in sensitivity to how they
fit with the circumstances of their speaking. Part of that is sensitivity to
how they need to fit in order to be true. So adequate sensitivity requires
grasping what truth is, and how that notion applies in particular cases. [ibid:
460]
This is where my understanding of the paper lapses. My
hunch is that for occasionalism to undermine deflationism the following would
have to be the case: fixing the understanding that words have on an occasion, and thus whether they are true of some circumstance, would itself have to
presuppose truth, or some feature of truth. That seems to fit with Travis’
words here: ‘Part of that is sensitivity [underpinning an understanding] to how
they need to fit in order to be true’. But I am not sure that I follow the
crucial thought – if I am at all on the right track – that this sensitivity
presupposes truth. The action must take place in section V.
But, there, the central example is of understanding the
utterance that ‘the oven is hot’ in the context of pizza making. In that
context it is reasonable to think that if the oven is merely 140C, then the
utterance is false. The context enables a reasonable perception of what is
being said when that phrase is used. But why does this presuppose a substantial
notion of truth? He says:
These perceptions of occasions are perceptions of what it
would be, on them, for a given description to describe truly, or for words
which give it to state truth; to provide information which is correct. Their
structure thus reveals some ingredients in truth, or what we are prepared to
recognize about it. Part of the idea of truth is that a description (of
something), to be true, must satisfy a general condition different in kind from
conditions to the effect that what is described as thus must be as thus described: it must serve all the
purposes that must be served (for truth) on that occasion, by having all the
uses it ought in serving them. Part of this idea is that, for a description,
and an occasion (on which there are facts as to what that description would
describe truly), there are definite purposes truth demands be served, and uses
which truth demands the description have in serving them. [ibid: 462-3]
If I follow, the idea seems to be that the
occasion-relative understanding must presuppose some notion of the description
being used truly in that context
(given one’s knowledge of the requirements of pizza cooking). But I am not sure that
this changes anything from the general worry that one cannot combine truth
conditional semantics with a deflationary approach to truth. There are two
familiar approaches to that: deploy a non-truth conditional approach to meaning
(like Horwich) or simply deny that either project is reductionst (like McDowell). Neither is simple, but I am not clear why occasionalism changes this.
Travis, C. (1996) ‘Meaning’s role in truth’ Mind 105: 451-66
Monday, 6 February 2012
The Inaugural Edgington Lectures - John McDowell on the Epistemology of Perception
THE EDGINGTON LECTURES
Professor John McDowell on the Epistemology of Perception
On March 2nd–3rd 2012, John McDowell will give two public lectures at Birkbeck College (London). The lectures will be given in the Birkbeck Main Building Room B33, Malet St., London, WC1E 7HX.
To register, email: edgingtonlectures@gmail.com
Friday 2nd March 18:15–20:00 PERCEPTION : OBJECTS AND CONTENTS
Saturday 3rd March 16:00–18:00 HOW PERCEPTION YIELDS KNOWLEDGE
The Saturday lecture will be followed by a reception in the Birkbeck Council Room, Main Building.
My rough notes on the lectures are here.
Professor John McDowell on the Epistemology of Perception
On March 2nd–3rd 2012, John McDowell will give two public lectures at Birkbeck College (London). The lectures will be given in the Birkbeck Main Building Room B33, Malet St., London, WC1E 7HX.
To register, email: edgingtonlectures@gmail.com
Friday 2nd March 18:15–20:00 PERCEPTION : OBJECTS AND CONTENTS
Saturday 3rd March 16:00–18:00 HOW PERCEPTION YIELDS KNOWLEDGE
The Saturday lecture will be followed by a reception in the Birkbeck Council Room, Main Building.
My rough notes on the lectures are here.
Subscribe to:
Posts (Atom)