Friday, 31 July 2009

Capacity, mental mechanisms and unwise decisions

I've been asked to contribute a commentary to a paper on the Mental Capacity Act to be assembled by ISCRI colleagues. Aware of the sophistication of Natalie Banner’s PhD thesis on this area, I've jotted down (in the second half of this morning) the following rather rough thoughts. Perhaps I can get a commentary out of them. Perhaps not. (Later: I've now benefitted from a conversation with Natalie and altered the text below.)

(August 2011: Here is the published paper.
Thornton, T. (2011) ‘Capacity, mental mechanisms and unwise decisions’ Philosophy Psychiatry and Psychology 18: 127-32)

Capacity, mental mechansisms and unwise decisions

Introduction

The notion of capacity implicit in the Mental Capacity Act is subject to a tension between two claims. On the one hand, capacity is assessed relative to a particular decision. It is the capacity to make one kind of judgement specifically, rather than another. So one can have capacity in one area whilst not having it in another. On the other hand, capacity is supposed to be independent of the ‘wisdom’ or otherwise of the decision made. (‘A person is not to be treated as unable to make a decision merely because he makes an unwise decision.’ [MCA 2005 section 1].) One may have capacity even if the decision one arrives at is seen as unwise by one’s doctor. In this short note I will explore this tension which is not at first apparent.

By saying that there is a tension between these two claims, I do not mean that they are inconsistent. They can both be true. But there is a natural way of thinking about the first claim, suggested by the second, which is false and accommodating both in its absence puts limits on just how atomic or decision specific capacity can be.

Capacity as the status of a process
Distinguishing between a lack of capacity and the making of unwise decisions helps escape the threat of medical paternalism. One can imagine a worry like this. Decision making capacity is assessed by the medical profession. Thus if a subject differs in their decisions from those thought best by their doctors, they are likely to be deemed, by that very fact, to lack the capacity to make that decision. And thus patient autonomy is undermined. One is likely only to be granted the status of having decision making capacity if one’s values accord with those of the medical profession. And hence the possibility of autonomous divergence is undermined.

That worry can be addressed by distinguishing between a lack of capacity and making merely an unwise decision. And that in turn suggests a notion of capacity which is distinguished from its outputs. One has capacity providing one follows the right process, whatever the particular output of that process is.

If capacity is not to collapse into the wisdom of the decision made, it is hard to see how else it can be construed except as a matter of using the right decision making process. But this suggests a problem. How, independently of the actual outcomes of the process, is the process itself to be first characterised and second assessed? This is not to say that the outcomes have no epistemic role. They may serve as evidence for (the identification of) the process. Still, if the process is to underpin the status of capacity (rather than the wisdom of the outcome), there had better be a way to characterise it which is independent of each output decision.

In the next section, I will outline the characterisation of process implicit in the Mental Capacity Act and use it to motivate an appeal to the idea of a mental mechanism to characterise a mental process in an outcome-independent way. In the section after that, I draw some arguments from Wittgenstein to criticise the very idea of a mental mechanism.

The process as suggested by the act
The Mental Capacity Act substantiates this notion of process in the following claims:

[A] person is unable to make a decision for himself if he is unable— (a) to understand the information relevant to the decision, (b) to retain that information, (c) to use or weigh that information as part of the process of making the decision, or (d) to communicate his decision (whether by talking, using sign language or any other means). ‘ [MCA 2005 section 3]

Not all of these, however, seem equally useful in specifying a process-based condition for decision making capacity. (Logical neatness would be provided by a stipulation of individually necessary and jointly sufficient conditions though there is no need to assume that that is the Act’s intent.)

Condition (a) seems a plausible necessary condition. Unless one can understand relevant information, how can one exercise epistemic responsibility? Further, it feeds naturally into (c) insofar as such (successful) understanding would be irrelevant if the decision in question were not actually based on it. But then, given (a) and (c), (b) now seems to be an unnecessary addition to the list. That is not to say that the condition it outlines is not necessary: the retention of information for sufficiently long, at least, to make the decision. But it now seems to be implicit in (c) since how could a decision be based by the subject on the relevant information understood in (a) if it were not retained long enough? Thus stipulating (b) looks to be unnecessary.

Condition (d) seems to be both peripheral and false. Undiagnosed sufferers of ‘locked in syndrome’ (confused perhaps from those in persistent vegetative state) may be unable to communicate their decisions to medical staff but it is implausible to say that that contingent fact undermines their capacity to make decisions. Of course, the inability in such a case is relational. The sufferer could communicate with the right (suitably informed) audience. What of cases where the inability supervenes on the state of the subject herself? Such a construal seems to make the condition irrelevantly weak since arguments for the necessity of the possibility at least of communication typically concern the possibility of possessing intentional states at all [eg Davidson, Dennett, Strawson]. In effect, on the assumption that such arguments for the necessity of the possibility of communication are successful then condition (d) threatens to undermine the decision making capacity of those without minds. That hardly needs saying. (To repeat: there is no reason to assume that the Act aims at an individually necessary and jointly sufficient condition to analyse capacity. There is, after all, a practical reason to deem a subject to be lacking in capacity if he or she cannot communicate. But that merely shows that condition (d) is of no help in explaining what is meant by ‘capacity’.)

Thus for the purposes of specifying a plausible outcome-independent process of decision making conditions (a) and (c) seem to be central. But now it is worth considering whether (a) makes a separable contribution to the jointly sufficient condition. One can imagine a case where (a) is satisfied without (c). Perhaps, for example, one can grasp behavioural information about an estranged lover sufficiently for it to feature as a premise in a variety of mundane arguments but not in the case of an argument to evaluate their continuing love. In that one context, wishful thinking undermines one’s ability to reason on the basis of such behavioural information.

But when (c) is satisfied, can (a) not be? That is, can the information be weighed as part of a decision making process without being understood? That seems doubtful. Note also that capacity is supposed to be assessed relative to a particular decision. Thus the relevant information need not be able to play a full inferential role across the board. It need not be fully inferentially promiscuous. Any reading of (a) that requires that cannot fit this constraint on capacity.

It seems, therefore, that condition (c) does all the work. One has capacity if it is satisfied and lacks it if it is not. How much does it help, however, with the specification of an output-independent process? At first sight it seems that it does. The decision making process can be thought of as, in part at least, a matter of ‘weighing information’. An ability to weigh information might contribute to an ability to make decisions even if, perhaps because of the poor quality of the information, it leads in any particular case to an unwise outcome. But whilst the idea of weighing information suggests that the process of forming a decision is mechanical it is so far merely a metaphor which needs further fleshing out. Further, there is a constraint to its fleshing out. For the end decision to be epistemically rational, the weighing of information has to be part of the process. This presents a challenge: what is the difference between information being weighed and then a decision being made (independently of it) and the decision being made on the basis of the weighing of information? The information has normatively to constrain the outcome but, as I will now suggest, there are good reasons drawn from Wittgenstein, to think that meeting this constraint through the idea of a mental mechanism fails.

The mind as a mechanism
Wittgenstein discusses the attractions and problems of the idea that mental processes are underpinned by mental mechanisms. One of the examples he considers is reading aloud. That process involves saying something on the basis of the text (to put things clumsily to make the parallel with condition (c) above clearer). And in such a case, one is inclined to think that there must be a fundamental difference in the underlying process between someone who can read aloud as a kind of ‘reading machine’ and someone just struggling to learn. They must embody different processes.

A person, let us say an Englishman, has received at school or at home one of the kinds of education usual among us, and in the course of it has learned to read his native language. Later he reads books, letters, newspapers, and other things.
Now what takes place when, say, he reads a newspaper?--His eye passes--as we say--along the printed words, he says them out loud--or only to himself; in particular he reads certain words by taking in their printed shapes as wholes; others when his eye has taken in the first syllables; others again he reads syllable by syllable, and an occasional one perhaps letter by letter.--We should also say that he had read a sentence if he spoke neither aloud nor to himself during the reading but was afterwards able to repeat the sentence word for word or nearly so.--He may attend to what he reads, or again--as we might put it--function as a mere reading-machine: I mean, read aloud and correctly without attending to what he is reading; perhaps with his attention on something quite different (so that he is unable to say what he has been reading if he is asked about it immediately afterwards).
Now compare a beginner with this reader. The beginner reads the words by laboriously spelling them out.--Some however he guesses from the context, or perhaps he already partly knows the passage by heart. Then his teacher says that he is not really reading the words (and in certain cases that he is only pretending to read them).If we think of this sort of reading, the reading of a beginner, and ask ourselves what reading consists in, we shall be inclined to say: it is a special conscious activity of mind…
But I want to say: we have to admit that--as far as concerns uttering any one of the printed words--the same thing may take place in the consciousness of the pupil who is ‘pretending’ to read, as in that of the practised reader who is ‘reading’ it. The word “to read” is applied differently when we are speaking of the beginner and of the practised reader.--Now we should of course like to say: What goes on in that practised reader and in the beginner when they utter the word can’t be the same. And if there is no difference in what they happen to be conscious of there must be one in the unconscious workings of their minds, or, again, in the brain.--So we should like to say: There are at all events two different mechanisms at work here. And what goes on in them must distinguish reading from not reading.--But these mechanisms are only hypotheses, models designed to explain, to sum up, what you observe. [Wittgenstein 1953 §§156]

Wittgenstein here begins to suggest that although one may be drawn to postulate a difference in mental mechanism, the conscious experience of the two readers (the skilled reader and the mere starter), may be the same. Thus as far as conscious experience is concerned, the same mental mechanism – the same experiences – may lead to different outcomes.

In the case of reading. the mental process has at its heart the idea of being guided in what one says (or thinks) by printed letters. Perhaps this notion – that of guidance – can be used to characterise a mental mechanism independently of its particular outcome but in such a way that it cannot help determine that outcome. Again there is reason to doubt it.

Make some arbitrary doodle on a bit of paper.--And now make a copy next to it, let yourself be guided by it.--I should like to say: “Sure enough, I was guided here. But as for what was characteristic in what happened--if I say what happened, I no longer find it characteristic.”But now notice this: while I am being guided everything is quite simple, I notice nothing special; but afterwards, when I ask myself what it was that happened, it seems to have been something indescribable. Afterwards no description satisfies me. It’s as if I couldn’t believe that I merely looked, made such-and-such a face, and drew a line.--But don’t I remember anything else? No; and yet I feel as if there must have been something else; in particular when I say “guidance”, “influence”, and other such words to myself. “For surely,” I tell myself, “I was being guided.”--Only then does the idea of that ethereal, intangible influence arise.
When I look back on the experience I have the feeling that what is essential about it is an ‘experience of being influenced’, of a connexion--as opposed to any mere simultaneity of phenomena: but at the same time I should not be willing to call any experienced phenomenon the “experience of being influenced”. (This contains the germ of the idea that the will is not a phenomenon.) I should like to say that I had experienced the ‘because’, and yet I do not want to call any phenomenon the “experience of the because”.
I should like to say: “I experience the because”. Not because I remember such an experience, but because when I reflect on what I experience in such a case I look at it through the medium of the concept ‘because’ (or ‘influence’ or ‘cause’ or ‘connexion’).--For of course it is correct to say I drew the line under the influence of the original: this, however, does not consist simply in my feelings as I drew the line--under certain circumstances, it may consist in my drawing it parallel to the other--even though this in turn is not in general essential to being guided.
—[Wittgenstein 1953 §§175-7]

There is no evidence from conscious experience here of a felt mechanism that links the signs to what one might say or do. Hence the prospects for characterising a kind of mental mechanism to explain a decision making process are dim. (Wittgenstein goes on to suggest that we apply the word ‘reading’ or ‘guidance’ on the basis of the performance of a speaker or agent. This is a normative relationship characterising input and output. It is not a mechanical connection between the two. I will return to this idea shortly.)

Wittgenstein raises a more fundamental objection to the idea of a psychological mechanism to explain such normative connections through a discussion of the ‘plus 2’ series, the series of numbers produced by starting at 0 and adding 2 sequentially. Having been suitably taught, children are able to carry this series on to arbitrarily high numbers. They can be said to understand the series, to have gasped it. Such understanding is ascribed despite what might seem to be a lack of evidence: the series – and thus the competence – is infinite whilst the ascription is based on only finite past practice. According to one commentator on Wittgenstein’s work, John McDowell, we tend to think of competence in continuing such a series as resulting from a psychological mechanism which reliably delivers the right result at each point. The misleading thought is this: postulating a psychological mechanism could explain why just the right numbers – out of the multitude of potential wrong numbers – are given for an infinite series. This picture can also be augmented, especially in mathematical cases, with the idea that the mechanism tracks or follows objective, perhaps supernatural, rails which are already out there, independently of us. Our continuing a series is merely going over, in bolder pencil, moves already made.

This line of argument rests on a mistake, however. It goes wrong in the assumption that it is necessary, or even helpful, to postulate a psychological mechanism to explain an ability to follow a rule. Postulating such a state of mind is an ‘idle wheel’ because it cannot ground the kind of expectation that either we, or other people, will continue in the same (successful) way. As Wittgenstein argues, if a direct inference from how someone has made judgements in the past to their future judgements were not reliable, postulating an intervening mechanism would not help either.

In the third person case of ascribing understanding to others, past practice, once described as mere inductive evidence for a mechanism, could be evidence for any number of diverging mechanisms. The same practice could be interpreted as being in accord with any number of different mechanisms.

In the first person case there is a problem in specifying the right mechanism to embody. Any real causal mechanism might misfire or breakdown and thus cannot be used to specify the correct continuation of the series. Any abstract representation of a mechanism, or any specification of the series using symbols, will require the correct interpretation which will beg the question.

Despite the attractions, the idea that mental processes are underpinned by mental mechanisms is a misleading one. So to return to the question at the end of the previous section – what is the difference between information being weighed and then a decision being made and the decision being made on the basis of the weighing of information? – whatever answer one gives, it cannot be a matter of specifying a mental mechanism independently of its output. Wittgenstein’s positive account of reading suggests instead that the ‘process’ of reading (if that is a helpful label) is defined by the general ability to get the words right and not by any inner experiences (which is not to deny that there are such experiences, however). The same, I suggest, holds for decision making capacity.

The tension again
I have suggested that there is a tension between two claims about decision making capacity: that it is domain specific and that it is independent of the wisdom or otherwise of its output. A natural way of spelling out the latter is to think of capacity as process-based. That in turn invites the idea that the process is underpinned by a mental mechanism. But it is hard to see how the latter idea can be unpacked and thus hard to see how it can be used to characterise a mental process independent of output. This suggests that the idea of a process of decision making is not a quasi-mechanical one but rather – like the idea of reading – one defined by a certain general ability, an ability or competence generally realised in performance.

The distinction between wisdom and capacity is provided by a partial independence of output from decision making process. Each individual decision could be unwise. But at the general level, a capacity reflecting ability to weigh information is an ability to make the right decision relative to it.

I can now summarise the tension. This approach to separating capacity and wisdom is in tension with the idea that capacity is decision-specific. The generality implicit in the former puts the latter idea under pressure. There are limits to how much capacity can be understood to be decision-specific.

Monday, 27 July 2009

An empirical test of the end of history?

Just before I went away, a number of my ISCRI colleagues met Mark Johnson (pictured) and Daniel Hutt to discuss potential joint research bids. Mark runs User Voice, an organisation which aims at reducing offender reoffending with the Saatchi & Saatchi slogan ‘only offenders can stop reoffending’.

Of the various projects discussed, one in particular struck me. They aim to improve the running of prisons through the formation of democratic structures within them, run by inmates. The model of democracy favoured is that of the council. Having already run significant pilot studies, they have substantial guidelines about how to educate both the electorate and those standing for election, with practical ideas that parties should represent views on particular areas of prison life, that those unsuccessful should still have a reserve role etc. Thus what the organisation brings to bear is expertise rather than just the idea of prison councils.

That said, the prime value of User Voice is that offenders themselves should play the most important role in any such initiative. And thus the guidelines offered by User Voice cannot be final: they cannot be structures imposed from without, from sideways on. It is up to the democratic process itself to determine its own form. This raises a nice question.

One of my colleagues asked, practically, what would be done to ensure that the democratic process would be inclusive: that those not directly involved would still informed, educated and kept in the loop? Mark Johnson’s reply was that versions of the process that were not inclusive would be voted out. Representatives who did not represent well would not succeed. In other words, his answer to a potential practical problem was that democracy itself would triumph without the active intervention of outside forces (his organisation, or mine, for example). But why think that?

I couldn’t help thinking that this is a reflection of Francis Fukuyama’s end of history thesis. Democracy would triumph over autocracy, for example, because of its own internal logic or value. The User Voice initiative may serve as a kind of empirical test of that idea.

Holiday holism

There is something inevitably depressing about returning to work after a holiday, no matter how much one enjoys one’s job. Despite the consolations of cheery colleagues, I’m relieved to be working from home today – a kind of half way stage – tackling the backlog in my email inbox: that tax on taking any time off. This experience always prompts the thought: what’s so special about holidays? Why can one not live as though on permanently on holiday?

I’ve returned from walking in the Canadian Rockies. Such First World outdoor orientated holidays fit a now well established template. In town: looking for decent coffee shops, nice pizza, the odd book or cd shop and micro-brewery beer. In the (nearby) country: day walks (rather than backpacking so as to allow opportunity for micro-brewery beer and pizza) up appealing mountains with perhaps some occasional bike or kayak hire.

On this trip, however, I realised that whilst that holiday template has been constant for some years (across, eg, several previous visits to Canada), my everyday life has itself increasingly converged on it. In other words, weekends, at least, involve the same goals of coffee, pizza, microbrewery beer and some decent hill walking, or a spin on the bike.

This is in part the result of general cultural changes in the UK. The Seattle Coffee Company – a UK chain – arrived as the first chain coffee shop whilst I lived in Leamington and by the time I left there were more than 20 in the town. Pizza Express, joined by Ask and Zizzi (again, Leamington had all three) have spread throughout the country even, finally, reaching Kendal. There has been a revolution in micro-brewing in the UK (there are 24 in Cumbria)…

(In the 1990s, if national breweries manufactured only tacky lager, microbreweries, encouraged by recent US legislation, provided an alternative. The antecedent is false in the UK – well, England – but the recent rise of microbreweries provides a kind of interesting local value.)

…But it also reflects my own relocation (to just outside the Lake District National Park).

Now, such convergence seems rational. It would be odd if the values expressed whilst on holiday were utterly distinct from those expressed during the rest of one’s life. That would be a kind of alienation of one's everyday state. But it does force the question of why the two kinds of set of otherwise the same practices seem so distinct from one another. One would never confuse them. I begin to think that there’s a kind of holism about holidays. Things simply have different meanings when away. In the context of a holiday, the practices have a different resonance. At the same time, the holiday just is the sum of the practices.

Tuesday, 7 July 2009

Capacity, wellbeing and mental health

Today’s Institute for Philosophy, Diversity and Mental Health colloquium took the theme of individual and community capacity and wellbeing. The key feature of these annual colloquia is the interplay of philosophy, psychiatry and a mental health service user voices. (The European service user group ENUSP holds its business meeting at Uclan immediately before.) But this presents a real challenge because, even within a meeting with obviously good intentions, there is going to be no easy reconciliation between active service users and working psychiatrists who have taken, so to speak, the King’s shilling.

Of course there are psychiatrists who, eg., eschew all diagnosis (when that is possible in view of the way mental healthcare is funded) and avoid drug treatments. But that is not the only approach taken by psychiatrists within the broader intellectual movement.

One general concern raised by Jan Verhaegh of ENUSP was how could members of service user organisations appear as subjects rather than objects of mental healthcare? In particular, he asked why, despite the broad concerns and range of sympathies manifested in the OUP IPPP series, were service user organisations not directly mentioned within it? Whatever the contingent reasons for this, the two concerns together suggest a tension in how to address the latter since simply being written about by others – me, for example – might itself form a kind of objectification.

During the course of the day I began to have a sense of how the two ‘dimensions’ (individual vs. community; and wellbeing and capacity: OK so not really a dimension) interacted asymmetrically. Whilst the work discussed at the community level readily suggested positive and interrelated notions of wellbeing and capacity (social or community capacity helping to underpin social or community wellbeing), at the individual level capacity seems to be something to be lost (measured, negatively, under the Mental Capacity Act) and wellbeing more naturally merely the absence of illness. Of course, it needn’t be seen like that but it will take some work to turn those habits of thought around.

See here for thoughts on capacity and unwise decisions.

Monday, 6 July 2009

Colour grammar

Tate Liverpool has an exhibition devoted to the rise of colour in recent and contemporary abstract art. Such exhibitions can do two things: chart the social history of art movements through the artworks displayed; and/or chart the visual possibilities: in this case the phenomenology of colour. There was some indication of the latter aim through reference in the exhibition and its presence in the bookshop of Goethe’s Theory of Colour. Strangely, though, interesting and enjoyable though it was, I don’t think I gained much of an insight into the possibilities of colour for art. I’m not sure that colour itself came across very well. But how could it? How could one chart colour simply by displaying it? (It’s not as though it’s missing from other art exhibitions.)

Many years ago I wrote one of the essays for my masters degree on Wittgenstein’s Remarks on Colour, which itself was influenced by Goethe’s work. Naomi Eilan kindly agreed to supervise me. I attempted to steer a minimalist course: seeing the comments on the absence of brown traffic lights or glowing grey as merely grammatical remarks needing no further underpinning but nevertheless providing real insight into the possibilities of colour itself (not merely ‘grammar’ on a pejorative understanding of that term). Every week, sitting in the Keynes room at King’s College (I seem to recall much stained glass and faintly pre-Raphaelite murals), drinking robustly black coffee, Naomi would listen to my efforts sadly and conclude the session with the words: ‘Next week, Tim we’ll have to get into some sexy metaphysics’.

Naomi, of course, has a particular project with a particular view of the possibilities of philosophical insight and explanation. But I wonder whether there is a more general worry about responding to Wittgenstein’s last work which sees it as importantly incomplete: a mere description of (some of) the phenomena but not getting at their somehow hidden underlying reality. Colour in particular seems to be an area where the gap between language as a medium of representation and what is represented seems greatest. (This may be related to the urge to think of colour in particular in appeals to qualia in the philosophy of mind.)

Thursday, 2 July 2009

Wellbeing

I’ve just read Mark Vernon’s short book Wellbeing in the Acumen Art of Living series: the same series as Havi Carel’s book Illness.

It’s a very interdisciplinary book drawing on some of the usual philosophical suspects (Aristotle, Plato, Kierkegaard), religious traditions, but also more recent empirical work by Layard and Seligman. It’s also quite chatty and a single train journey would be enough to read it. But I’m unconvinced by the central message.

There’s a basic trajectory starting with a discussion of the importance of happiness and utilitarian calculations. But happiness in itself is too shallow a notion and hence wellbeing is selected. Wellbeing involves more than just happiness. It also requires some notion of meaning.

So wellbeing is a better word because it draws attention to the centrality of meaning. However, that alone is not enough. For meaning itself forces us to ask the question: what is good? This, I think, moves the discussion on again. In turn, it pushes us towards the matter of the transcendent. The connection was obvious for the ancients. the good, like the truth, was ultimately a perception that only the gods could enjoy. However, humans could touch the transcendent because of, as Aristotle put it, “the divine within us”: the capacity for higher flourishing. They had faith that it was possible for human beings to share in it, if someone lives right….Our question has changed again: if meaning matters on what does it rest today? [Vernon 2008: 48-9]

Vernon considers and – I think! – rejects attempts to articulate a kind of immanent transcendence within human practices and projects. Of Peter Singer’s finding a form of transcendence in concern for animals and the environment, Vernon says: ‘I do not think he is wrong so much as wonder whether he has said enough’ [ibid: 77]. But he also says he writes as an agnostic. And this pushes him to think that the transcendence that underpins the meaning of everyday practices has itself to be a kind of mystery, merely pointed towards. Wellbeing is encouraged by thinking of life as underpinned by a deeper reality. But that ‘reality’ is mysterious.

The closest we get to an account of this is as follows:

It might be thought paradoxical that mystery provides meaning, as opposed to a complete understanding. Is it not natural to think that if life is to have meaning, that meaning should be found in life, not outside it? The reason it might, though, stems from the fact that human understanding is limited, and so the meaning human understanding can provide is inevitably limited too. To be human is to find ways of talking about what you don’t know as well as what you do. Perhaps an analogy with music is helpful. In What to Listen for in Music, the composer Aaron Copland wrote: “The whole problem can be stated quite simply by asking, ‘Is there a meaning to music?’ My answer to that would be, ‘Yes’. And ‘Can you state in so many words what the meaning is?’ My answers to that would be, ‘No’”. [ibid: 79]

The first part of this answer seems to trade on a dark notion of mystery which both can and cannot be grasped. It is as though whatever might underpin the meaning of our lives is merely beyond view. But it is not clear that anything could help here. (One can imagine a question akin to Moore’s open question.) The second part connects meaning to musical understanding as Wittgenstein also does. But the sense of meaning in music will not help in this case. It is as though Vernon appeals to a kind of meaning which might be linguistic but somehow just fails: a meaning that we can (with echoes of Ramsey’s sarcasm) just about whistle.

Vernon, M. (2008) Wellbeing, Stocksfield: Acumen